
Dick
Howard’s The Specter of Democracy is composed primarily
of recent essays revised for this volume. They express ideas
that he has been developing for about three decades. Cutting a
broad swath, he critically explores the relations between
theory, history, and politics. The essays reflect his
intellectual journey—his early engagements with Marx, the
Frankfurt School, and, especially, Claude Lefort and Cornelius
Castoriadis, his later works on politics, political judgment,
and French and American political history, and his current
ideas about Marx and political theory after communism.
Howard’s post-Marxist theoretical argument provides a
connective thread in the loosely integrated essays. He states
that re-engaging Marx is timely in a “post-1989 world that
wants to replace political choice by submission to the
‘natural necessity’ of the market.”1
He contends that Marx’s effort to conjure up proletarian
revolutionary subjectivity from technical progress and
economic crisis has a similar “antipolitical” thrust. Howard
(p. 10) holds that “Marx was essentially a philosopher,” but
that his attempt to radically historicize Hegelianism,
translating it into a materialist theory of historical
rationality and social progress, subordinated his
philosophical critique of alienation to a deterministic
“sociology.”2
According to Howard, Marx’s practice of “philosophy by other
means”obscured the normative nature of his critique, conflated
the realm of freedom with necessity, and blinded him to the “democratic
political implications of his own analysis” (emphasis in
the original). Howard attempts to execute a complicated
theoretical maneuver; he criticizes Marx’s sociological
reduction of politics in order to recover the “philosophical
Marx” and, then, ultimately go beyond him “to open the path to
politics” and democracy that he sees to be absent in Marx (p.
xiii).
Howard acknowledges considerable debt to Lefort and
Castoriadis, devoting several chapters to their ideas and
employing them throughout the book. Increasingly skeptical
about communism after the suppressed 1956 Hungarian revolt,
they and others in the Socialisme ou Barbarie circle
declared the autonomy of politics from economic determination,
engaged new forms of protest that went beyond class, and
brought to the foreground communist repression, which
generally had been ignored by the French left. As Howard
explains, Lefort and Castoriadis saw Hegelian historicism to
be a root of Marx’s reductive claim that progressive
development of the mode of production leads inevitably to
emancipation. Rather than an advance over Hegelian idealism,
they argued, his materialism grants pseudohistorical necessity
to contingent historical processes. Stressing an affinity for
totalitarianism, they held that Marx’s historicism has been
deployed by communist regimes and parties to justify the
suppression of political opposition. Howard shares their view
that Marxism neutralizes its own democratic political
potentiality and that realization of it requires a radical
break with historicism and a new openness to history.
Howard also agrees with Lefort’s definition of the political
as the “symbolic institution of society,” or creation and
reproduction of the normative bases of societal institutions.
Lefort held that pre-existing hierarchical societies limited
these symbolic practices to élites, who fashioned “external or
transcendent” religious and metaphysical legitimations to
justify their dominance. As Howard explains, he argued that
democracy seeks “unity from within” society and expects its
“members to take responsibility for their own individuality.”
Lefort held that democracy arose when the ancien régime
collapsed and citizens asserted the “right to have rights,” or
the right to demand from the state recognition of their
individual rights. He portrayed democracy as a plural “public
space” where diverse citizens and groups, empowered by their
rights, engage in open-ended, historically-variable
deliberations. In his view, the consequent “radical
indeterminacy” rules out unified publics and determination by
general social conditions. However, Lefort contended that
these reductionist ideas are products of modern ideologies,
which arise to ease uncertainty and mask contingency. For
example, liberalism’s claims about a rational self-interested
subject and the inevitable operations of “market forces”
provide a sense a certainty about liberal society’s
foundations that discourage consideration of political
alternatives. Lefort believed that an independent, open civil
society is the best bulwark against the ideological reflex’s
antipolitics. Following Lefort, Howard holds that Marx’s
sociological reduction and vision of materially-driven
proletarian unity deny politics’ discursive, contingent
nature and that these historicist ideas, combined with Marx’s
highly negative view of civil society and liberal rights,
constitutes a proto-totalitarian ideology (pp. 77-80,
116-18,166, 209-10, 327, note 10).
Howard states that Castoriadis acknowledged that “Marx bet on
history and lost” (i.e., his hopes about the emancipatory
proletariat failed). Howard implies, however, that Castoriadis
still carried on the Marxist project to transcend Hegelianism
with the understanding that it required a much more radical
break than Marx was willing to make. Howard shares
Castoriadis’s goal of moving beyond historicist teleology to a
position recognizing history’s uniqueness, autonomy, and
contingency (pp. 87-88). By contrast, Howard argues, the
Frankfurt School failed to make this decisive post-Marxist,
post-Hegelian move and, when their revolutionary hopes
crashed, they sought aesthetic transcendence and rejected
“everyday politics” (pp.39-41). Howard speculates that their
deeply pessimistic vision of consumer capitalism’s seamlessly
integrated, depoliticized, “one-dimensional” culture helped
inspire later postmodernist claims about the end of modernity
and exhaustion of politics. In his view, this “antipolitics”
or “politics of theory” manifest constricted political vision,
rather than politics’ actual demise. Howard explains his
youthful affiliation with Telos, stressing the initial
trouble that he had getting that formerly left journal, which
was then still operating in Marx’s tracks, to take up Lefort
and Castoriadis. He did not mention, however, that the editor
and his inner circle, at that time, posed an extreme version
of the one-dimensionality thesis portraying a near total
closure of historical contradictions and of immanent
possibilities for progressive change. This view not only
anticipated pessimistic forms of postmodernism, but the
Telos inner circle’s consequent search for organic
community led them to take up Carl Schmitt in the 1980s and,
after, to make an anti-liberal, neopopulist turn.
Howard devotes considerable attention to historical comparison
of French and American political cultures. He holds that the
framers of the French republican regime had to pose a new
conception of unity to replace the old monarchy’s lost
integration. Faced with the problem of fragmentation, Howard
contends, they envisioned a republican state reviving
political unity. He argues that the framers of the new French
regime stressed inclusion at the national level, calling for
universal citizenship and state action to insure social and
political rights and to secure social equality. By contrast,
he explains, engaging a setting that lacked the ancien
régime’s cultural and political unity, American framers
forged a vision of a self-managed democracy that is composed
of diverse communities and individuals and that secures
inclusion through free association and minimal reliance on
state power. He holds that adoption of judicial autonomy and
competitive political parties made clear that rights had to be
won and defended politically. Howard embraces American
“republican democracy,” which he sees to be inherently
pluralist, open, and dynamic, while he implies that the
state-centered French “democratic republic” is prone to the
sociological reduction and proto-totalitarian singularity that
he says inheres in Marxism. Still, he argues that American
democracy may also express antipolitical tendencies; e.g., its
emphasis on individual rights can degenerate into a
“procedural republic” manifesting “right over good,” legal
formality, and social fragmentation. In his view, the
republican idea in France as well as in the United States is
“political” rather than “socio-economic” and, thus, can be
employed critically against the sociological reduction and
collective subjects (pp. 174, 184). Howard’s historical
accounts of French and American republicanism are too complex
to adequately summarize here. However, their unifying thread
is emphatic critique of the reduction of discursively-mediated
political action to general sociological contexts and fictive
collective subjects, which he implies deprive politics of
their historical particularity and complex, dynamic, plural,
dispersed agency.
Howard speaks briefly about a totalizing “politics of will”
that posits— independent of political action—a “right thing to
be done” and a “unified actor” to do it and about an opposed
“politics of judgement” that reflects critically on the
consequences of political action and acts prudently. Stressing
the need to take “responsibility” for political decision,
which the politics of will abjures, Howard suggests that the
politics of judgement suffuse republican democracy and his own
analyses (pp. 18-22, 30, 78, 74, 107, 194-96). He also
mentions in passing Max Weber’s related “ethics of conviction”
and “ethics of responsibility” (p. 236). These concepts were
part of Weber’s broader post-traditional argument about
political responsibility, which rejected ideas of historical
necessity and collective subjects and the consequent aversion
of political decision. Moreover, Weber warned that fanatical
forms of conviction suspend ethical reflection as well as
political prudence, justifying extreme control, violence, and
repression and giving rise to the total state. Addressing
Weber might have prompted Howard to clarify his concepts of
politics of will and politics of judgment, which are central
to his argument, but are left unelaborated. John Dewey’s
radical democratic theory also seems to converge at key points
with Howard’s project. Dewey stressed democracy’s uncertain,
plural, discursive, historically particular, incomplete,
experimental nature. He aimed to fashion a radically
historicist, antifoundationalist democratic alternative to
Hegelian historicism that breaks as fundamentally from modern
ideas of historical necessity as it does from traditional
metaphysics, religion, and political philosophy. Also, Dewey
posed his mature social theory contra totalitarianism—Fascism
and Stalinism. Engaging Dewey critically also might have
sharpened Howard’s argument. However, his failure to address
these particular thinkers is not problematic per se. Rather,
the problem is that he does not situate adequately his theory
relative to related political theories and social theories.
Developing this theoretical context would have helped Howard
bring forward more clearly and completely his overall position
on democracy and its connections to current historical and
political contexts.
Howard’s unqualified claims about the “autonomy” and “radical
indeterminacy” of politics and negative comments about “the
flat terrain of sociology” and the “mere sociologist” (pp. 77,
81) draw an overly sharp boundary between politics and its
“sociological” contexts. Exaggerating the threat of
sociological reduction, he largely ignores the interdependence
between these relatively autonomous spheres. Moreover,
he does not distinguish the pseudo-sociology employed in bogus
historicist arguments from genuine sociological inquiry about
conditions that influence the direction and content of
politics. He recognizes passingly that sociological analysis
may have a limited role in normative critique, but he does not
explain that role and, being very wary of the “totalitarian
temptation,” he asserts that such analysis easily turns
reductive (p. 134). He also implies that a sociological moment
in normative critique would be positivist, suggesting the kind
of disembodied eye, oblivious to normative conditioning of
social inquiry, that thinkers like Weber and Dewey dismissed
early last century. By contrast, Howard does not acknowledge
that philosophy, which he strongly privileges in political
critique, may need a sociological moment to avert the very
tendency “to fly above reality” that he attributes to
positivism. Strong claims about autonomy may inhere in efforts
to make radical breaks from powerful constraints, but these
moves still manifest the sociological context. Lefort’s and
Castoriadis’s emphatic claims about autonomy and indeterminacy
make sense in light of their effort to break politically,
intellectually, and even personally from post-World War II
communism and from its patently constrained politics and
sterile deterministic theories. However, this context has
faded long ago. Today, politically ambiguous Schmitteans and
populists as well as “New Right” proto-fascists make similar
strong claims about the autonomy of politics and attack
sociological reduction in their critiques of globalization and
neoliberalism. Howard surely opposes such positions, but the
context of his own work is not clear and he does not explain
its political relevance.
Howard recognizes the problem. He says that he does “not want
to leave the impression that the theoretical arguments
presented here have no immediate political implications,” and
he invites readers to his website to sample some of his recent
“directly political” commentaries, which he says illustrate
his “understanding of democracy as radical.” I accepted his
invitation, but his many well-reasoned points about the
American political climate in the wake of 9/11 do not clarify
the political direction of his overall argument and,
especially, why it should be construed to be an extension of
Marx or to be radically democratic. Howard analyzes how
historicism and sociological reduction contribute to
de-politicization and de-democratization, but he explains
neither the current relevance of his strong claims about
autonomy nor his overall substantive vision of
democracy. Like Dewey, he stresses an affinity between
historicism and democracy, but, by contrast to Dewey, he does
not offer tools for a critique of “really existing”
democracy—e.g., to evaluate whether the United States has
“strong” or “weak” republican democracy and to suggest how it
might be made “stronger” and more just. This is an ironic
problem for a thinker who endorses political critique and
democracy so enthusiastically.
The issue of historicity and sociology brings us back to Marx.
Howard’s critique of historical necessity addresses a deeply
problematic thread in Marx’s work. However, he implies that
determinism rules Marx’s analysis of capitalism. Howard does
not acknowledge the side of Marx’s work that stresses
sociological inquiry into the specific conditions of
particular situations (i.e., recognizing the contingent nature
of the social) and that employs concepts as heuristic devices
(simplifying a contingent empirical world for analytical
purposes). Even young Marx countered his Hegelian side with
points about the need to study “definite individuals” sharing
historically-specific social and political relations. However,
the materialist transparency promised at the end of the
Manifesto’s famous passage about “all that is solid melts
into air” is replaced, in his mature work, by a warning that
the “appearance of simplicity vanishes.” In Capital,
Marx spoke of an “economistic law of motion” operating with
“iron necessity” and leading “inevitably” to proletarian
emancipation. However, he also held that proliferation of
“middle and intermediate strata,” in England, “obliterate
lines of demarcation everywhere.” He understood that advanced
capitalism’s complex class relations and interventionist state
posed problems for his political hopes and that his social
theory had to be brought to bear on increasingly diverse types
of capitalism. Late in life, Marx even doubted that full
capitalist modernization would extend beyond western Europe.
His sociological uncertainty appears in other forms. For
example, he conditioned his core materialist idea that the
pumping out of surplus product from direct producers is “the
hidden basis of the entire social structure” with the
qualification that the process has “infinite variations and
gradations in appearance, which can be ascertained only by
analysis of the empirically given circumstances.” Similar
qualifications about empirical variability appear in other
parts of Capital, implying that Marx saw his theory as
a heuristic model as well as the mirror of the Telos of
History. The point is that Marx expressed two types of
“historical” narratives—sociological historicism and Hegelian
historicism. Howard criticizes sharply Marx’s historicism, but
his position should be evaluated in the broader light of the
tensions between and entwinement of his determinism and his
sociology.
Engels admitted after Marx’s death that he and Marx had
exaggerated the “economic side,” but he also declared famously
that their materialist method claimed nothing more than: “the
ultimately determining element in history is the
production of and reproduction of real life.” Holding that
“all history must be studied afresh,” Engels insisted that
they created “a guide to study, not a lever after the manner
of the Hegelian.”3
Engels’s afterthought understates the determinist thread in
Marx’s and his materialism, but it stresses correctly the
importance of their sociological historicism. The master
narrative of their texts is still a matter of debate. However,
Howard’s privileging of the “philosophical Marx” and reducing
of his sociological side to Hegelianism understates the
significance of his sociology. The enduring value of Marx’s
work derives as much from his sociology as from his normative
ideas. His analysis of capitalism poses still compelling
questions about its highly problematic relationship with
democracy. His view that socio-economic matters condition
fundamentally the shape, quality, and possibility of democracy
and, thus, need to be taken account of in theory and practice
does not by itself constitute a sociological reduction of
politics. By contrast, unqualified emphasis on the autonomy of
politics does not favor inquiry into the impacts of wealth and
power on democracy, which are often concealed or intentionally
suppressed. Addressing the impacts of expanded corporate power
and increased economic inequality, under neoliberal
globalization, is essential to today’s debates over the
prospects for democracy and does not preclude the relative
autonomy of politics or deny other forms exclusion. A theory
of radical democracy must bring to the foreground the unequal
and unjust distribution of the material and cultural means of
participation. Marx’s impassioned emphasis on this matter
gives him more than nine lives and is the reason that his
specter still hangs over us today. In this light, Howard’s
emphasis on the importance of Marx’s normative side makes
sense. But Marx’s vision of capitalist inequality is the main
point of conjuncture between his philosophy and sociology—his
sociology provides his normative vision of justice specificity
and historicity. That Howard is silent about the relation of
capitalism and democracy raises questions about the
methodological adequacy as well as the historicity of his
claims about the autonomy of politics and his dim view of the
sociological moment of criticism.
Arguably Marx founded the tradition of modern “social theory.”
Social theorists frame normative arguments, but their work is
distinguished from earlier types of normative theory by a
strong sociological moment. Although the borders are fluid,
social theory’s normative thrust distinguishes it from more
narrowly-focused, empirically-oriented “sociological theory”
and social science. By contrast to religion and metaphysics
the legitimacy of social theory depends on the
discursively-mediated, empirical-historical validity of its
“sociological” claims as well as the consistency,
persuasiveness, and emotional/aesthetic force of its normative
facets. Social theory’s project of providing an “historical”
alternative to absolutist normative argument is neither
complete nor transparent. First-generation social theorists,
like Marx, often conflated History with history and tried to
justify their practice as “science,” obscuring its normative
thrust. Howard rightly criticizes this reduction, which is
still a problem today. However, as in Marx’s case, social
theorists’ historicist and scientistic claims have often
appeared alongside, in the same texts, valid types of
sociological and normative argument. Today, after multiple
waves of critiques of scientism, theorists sometimes deny or
understate social theory’s empirical-historical side and,
thus, lean back toward absolutism or simply fail to justify
their normative practices at all. Howard does not make this
error, but he suggests a rather narrowly construed conception
of political theory that understates the role of sociological
contexts in conditioning political action and political
thought. The interdependence of the sociological and political
moments call for a broader view of theory that takes fuller
account of the fact that democracy is a “social thing.”
That confusion still reigns over the nature of social theory
and its boundaries with empirical-historical work has been
easy to see in later 20th century polemics over postmodernism
and other interdisciplinary theories. Opposing sides in these
disputes have often pitted science and social theory against
each other. By contrast, these practices, regardless of their
independent logics, are culturally entwined; social theory
provides a post-traditional language to debate the normative
directions of science and policy and social science provides
the historical knowledge for social theory arguments, in which
normative justification depends largely on claims about the
socio-cultural and political consequences of the proposed
policy regimes. Howard’s critique of historicism contributes
to the project of social theory. His points about the
sociological reduction eroding political responsibility and
sapping democratic vitality likely has as much cultural
significance after communism, as they did when Lefort and
Castoriadis posed their ideas. Recall Howard’s passing comment
that his critique of Marxist antipolitics is relevant to
neoliberalism; its collective subject, the rational
economizer, and claims about the inevitable impacts of “market
forces” suggest an abdication of political decision parallel
to that generated by Marxist certainty about the emancipatory
proletariat and communism. Hopefully, Howard will follow up on
this provocative point, bringing to bear his broader argument
about the political on neoliberalism, which will likely make
his position clearer and perhaps answer the concerns that I
have raised.
Notes
1
Dick Howard, The Specter of Democracy (New York:
Columbia University Press, 2002), p. 287. Further page
references to this work are in parentheses in the text of
this essay.
2
“Sociology” is used here to refer to social science,
rather than to the explicit discipline of sociology.
Howard identifies Marx’s “economic” theory as
“sociological.” Marx’s historical materialism focuses on
the social relationships by which ruling or
dominant classes extract surplus from direct producers.
His “labor theory of value” addresses the capitalist
version of this social relationship.
3
Frederick Engels, “Engels to Conrad Schmidt” and “Engels
to Joseph Bloch” (Letters written in 1890), pp.395-400 in
Marx and Engels: Basic Writings on Politics and
Philosophy, edited by Lewis S. Feuer (Garden City, NY:
Anchor Books, 1959).
Robert J. Antonio
is professor of Sociology at the University of Kansas.
|