
n the 1980s, with several
friends, I helped produce a radio program called “Europe-in-Formation” in
the New York left-wing public radio station WBAI. This was a time well
before the ultimate internal weakness of the Soviet Union became apparent
and when a true or good or purified socialism remained a hope for many
leftists. Our idea was that the model of a European Union, enlarging the
welfare state and challenging the realpolitik cynicism of a U.S.
government that supported repressive regimes in the name of fighting the
communist enemy would encourage political criticism that was still
leftist even while it contained a dose of realism. The process by which
Europe was coming into being was to serve as an inspiration for the
creation of a left that was at once democratic and social.
Two decades later, the
question of Europe remains relevant but the challenge it poses is
different. Whereas the left had been the stubborn victim of its own
ideological dreams or hopes, today, after the end of the Cold War and
with the victory of liberalism and capitalism, there is no serious left
wing political project. In the earlier moment, the left was full of
ideas, inventing Projects (with a capital P) and knitting together the
undeniably important but always partial, and often temporary, successes
into a global vision. Today, the left has few ideas; its politics
consists in opposing the most egregious elements of the economic free-marketeers
and the attempts by social reactionaries to roll back the achievements of
modernity.
The European idea has gained
some attractiveness as, even in the countries that Secretary of Defense
Rumsfeld refers to as the “new” Europe, healthy majorities have appeared
to oppose the pre-emptive unilateralism of the U.S. foreign policy. On
the other hand, that “old” Europe has been denounced—not without some
grounds—as the weak-kneed “Venus” whose well-being depends on the
military strength of the American “Mars.” What is more, in at least some
countries (such as France), large minorities within the orbit of the
socialist party considered seriously the idea of voting against the
ratification of an eventual European constitution if it were put to vote
in a referendum. Europe seemed to them the vehicle of an expanded
capitalism; its advances in the sphere of human rights standing only as a
concession to liberalism. Europe, from this perspective, is said to
suffer from a “democratic deficit”—although it is often not clear just
what is meant by this vague concept.
In order to get some
perspective on the status and implications of the European model today, I
propose to return to the old distinction between two kinds of liberalism,
and the two models of democratic politics with which they are associated.
The roots of this distinction are both historical and conceptual, while
its manifestations can be seen in the contemporary political cultures of
the Europeans and the Americans.
One appealing approach to the
Euro/American distinction between the two cultures is suggested by Pierre
Hassner, who traces the difference back to the geo-political fact that
Europe is a continent composed of nations defined by their borders, which
entails the need to form alliances and to understand the need to maintain
a balance of power, whereas America is a continent that can chose
isolation, decide when to use force or can opt to employ the peaceful
arms of commerce. As a result, Europe has learned to recognize the
usefulness of rules that bind sovereignty, while ensuring that war is
limited to those who are actually fighting, whereas the U.S. refuses to
accept limits on its sovereign will and, when it does go to war, it
accepts no constraints (such as worry about “collateral damage). Old
Europe calls the agreed-on rules “civilization,” while virile young
America treats them as limits, and denounces them as a sign of weakness
of will.[i]
This difference is manifest, for example, in the different attitudes
toward the creation of an International Court of Justice.
A return to the historical
roots of America’s republican democratic culture illustrates the
difficulty of overcoming the unitary temptations of what I have called a
politics of will. Twelve years after the ratification of the new
constitution, Thomas Jefferson was elected president in what
contemporaries called “the revolution of 1800.” The term is surprising,
and it has fallen out of use by historians.[vi]
Since Jefferson’s support for the French revolution was well-known, it
led to the belief that he would bring social change, a kind of American
version of 1793. What was in fact revolutionary was not the social
content of Jefferson’s politics, but rather the political fact that
power passed peacefully from one political party to another. This had
never happened before; it was made possible by the unique political
culture that was described at the outset of this argument: “the” people
(in their plurality and difference) are represented in all the
institutions of the republic, which means, therefore, that they are
incarnated in none. But Jefferson’s republicans themselves did not
understand this republican democracy, as they showed shortly thereafter
when they refused to confirm the (“midnight”) appointment by the outgoing
government of a federal magistrate. They, after all, were now the
democratically elected majority who, they assumed, represented the actual
will of the people and were not bound by the action of the previous
majority. In 1803, in Marbury v. Madison, the Supreme Court issued
the decision that was the foundation of its own independent power—a power
that, like all powers in the United States, is based on the
constitution rather than on the will of any temporary majority.
These two institutional
innovations were made possible by the culture of a republican democracy.
The foundation of that political culture can be understood by its
contrast to the forms of the politics of will. It rests on what can be
called a politics of judgment that begins from the plurality of
rights-bearing individuals in order to make possible a kind of solidarity
that need not claim to incarnate the unitary will of a homogeneous
nation. Leaving aside the philosophical foundations of this concept, its
institutional form can be described in general terms by a closer look at
the American constitutional practice of republican democracy. At issue is
the relation between the particularity and plurality of socio-economic
relations and the juridical-political framework that unifies society. On
the one hand, political parties articulate particular problems that
emerge within civil society and aggregate them in the form of a proposed
law. The temptation for the parties is to reach for the lowest common
denominator, and to avoid issues that concern only minorities, with the
result that the laws may prove inadequate to protect the rights of this
or that group or individual. At this point, the Court enters the picture,
providing a republican check to ensure that the temporary legislative or
executive majority cannot claim to incarnate once-and-for-all the vox
populi. This interaction of particular and universal can be repeated
in the other direction. There will be times when political debate is
blocked, issues appear too hot to handle; and at this point the Court
intervenes, this time in order to make certain that the particular is not
blocked from debate. Now it becomes the task of the parties to find a way
to deal with the issue at the level of the everyday political life of the
citizenry (rather than at the constitutional level).[vii]
Two conclusions and a
caveat follow from this comparative account. The caveat is
most important. It insists that the cultural politics of judgment is not
attained once and for all; a fall back to the politics of will is always
possible. One cannot expect to introduce (or impose) the American
institutional structure in foreign contexts, as if their own political
culture and history did not matter. What one can learn from the American
experience is what kind of political culture would satisfy the structural
imperatives of a politics of judgment. This permits a negative
conclusion. The hope that “Europe” will become that third way formerly
identified with the economic policies of “Social Democracy” will
not be realized. As indicated at the outset, the problem for a liberal
political culture is not to add social and material predicates to the
formal rights of the individual; the problem, rather, is to imagine and
understand the new forms of solidarity that, paradoxically in the
eyes of some, are based on the individual right to have rights. Europeans
need to look at their achievements since the 1956 Rome Treaty with an eye
toward finding the functional equivalent of the American politics of
judgment. Meanwhile, from their side, the Americans have something to
learn from the “civilized” political culture of modern Europe (which
Pierre Hassner, in search of a ringing paradox, too quickly identifies
with postmodernism). A republican democracy, after all, is only possible
when it gives itself rules that limit its will while making necessary the
exercise of judgment and the assumption of responsibility for it.
Contemporary America seems to have forgotten that basic lesson.
Notes
[i]
The debate between such “civilization” and the virile energy of
nature can be found already among Greek sophists such as Callicles.
It reappears as the Roman republic becomes Hellenized . . . before it
rediscovers its supposed virility and becomes the world-encompassing
Empire. The astonishing parallels between Roman history and that of
America are well-illustrated by Peter Bender in Weltmacht Amerika.
Das neue Rom (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 2003).
[ii]
C.f., Gordon Wood, The Radicalism of the American Revolution. How
a Revolution transformed a Monarchical Society into a Democratic one
Unlike any that had Ever Existed (New York: Knopf, 1992). The
subtitle of this fascinating book points to the thesis expressed
here, since “monarchical” implies the existence of a
status-hierarchy.
[iii]
I am equating “French” with “European” for the sake of simplicity.
[iv]
It might be noted that this refusal to admit that any power can
incarnate the sovereign will of the people explains why, in the long
run, America will prove to be incapable of becoming a truly imperial
power.
[v]
It is worth noting that the chief negotiator of the Helsinki Accords,
Henry Kissinger, did not intend the so-called “third basket” that
treated human rights to be taken seriously; he was operating within a
realpolitik framework that sought to make permanent détente.
[vi]
I have been able to find only one book specifically devoted to the
theme. C.f., Daniel Sisson, The American Revolution of 1800
(New York: Knopf, 1974). The book is out of print, and the author
seems to have written no other book since that time.
[vii]
Illustrations of this process in recent history concern such
questions of racial integration, sexual (or gender) discrimination,
the rights of women and other minorities. Such contemporary
illustrations may suggest that 19th century politics, particularly in
the period leading to, and then emerging from the Civil War, were at
best only approximations to the kind of republican democracy that has
come to exist in the 20th century.
Dick
Howard
is Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at SUNY Stony Brook. His
most recent book is
The Specter of Democracy
(Columbia University Press).
|