
As he ate with friends
at a Paris café on the evening of July 31, 1914, Jean Jaurès
was shot and killed. One day later, Germany declared war on
Russia and the French government ordered a massive military
mobilization. Three days later, Germany declared war on
France. On the fourth day, the day that Germany invaded
neutral Belgium and Great Britain declared war on Germany,
the head of France’s trade union confederation rose at
Jaurès’s funeral to say:
Friend Jaurès! You,
the apostle of peace, of international harmony, depart at
the hour when the most terrible epic of war that has ever
bloodied Europe commences before a dismayed world. You were
a victim of your ardent love for humanity. Your eyes will
not see the red glow of the flames, the hideous jumble of
corpses that the bullets have laid to rest on the ground.
Jaurès had
worked tirelessly against the impending war, and his
assassination marked the last moment at which hope for peace
seemed possible. The First World War may have obliterated
the nineteenth century’s hopes of endless and inevitable
progress, but this is not the only kind of hope. If we
reexamine the ideas Jaurès sought to realize through his
scholarship and political involvement, we can retrace the
structure of his hope, and we might find that his kind of
hope is appropriate to our times.
Auguste-Marie-Joseph-Jean
Jaurès was born to a modest bourgeois family on September 3,
1859, in the city of Castres. Jaurès’s hometown was a small
provincial center of trade and manufacturing set in a rural
agricultural region where heavy industry had only recently
arrived. As a youth, Jaurès was a bright and determined
student. He entered the Ecole Normale in 1879, graduating
third in his class in 1881.
After four
years of teaching philosophy at a lycée in Albi and
then at the University of Toulouse, Jaurès plunged into
politics. He was the youngest member of Parliament when he
took his seat after the 1885 elections as a delegate for the
region around Castres, Albi, and Toulouse. French
parliamentary politics in the 1880s was fundamentally a
conflict between republican advocates of rationalism and
constitutional democracy and reactionaries nostalgic for
monarchy and protective of Church prerogatives. Schooled in
philosophy but ignorant of the inordinate complexity of
French factional politics, unsure of anything but his
commitment to the Republic and to the Rights of Man, Jaurès
took a seat with the delegates of the largest republican
faction, voted loyally with them, and attracted little
attention to himself.
Seventy
years after Jaurès entered Parliament, Ignazio Silone wrote
about the “choice of comrades” that precedes political
ideology, a choice that is “emotional, beyond logic” and
that is only later subjected to rational examination. Jaurès
made his choice of comrades during his first term in office.
He quickly became impatient with the political caution and
moral hollowness of the centrist republican politicians.
There were a half-dozen socialists on the left fringe of
Parliament, but Jaurès found them doctrinaire and
simplistic. Exploring the district he represented, however,
he met and talked with members of the miners’ and
glass-makers’ unions. He traveled, asked questions, read,
observed, and soon found himself drawn toward the labor
movement. In 1886, he spoke at the congress of the miners’
federation. In 1887, he led a parliamentary fight for safety
protections in the mines, and worked—without much success—to
introduce pensions, accident and sickness insurance, and
other social welfare measures that would benefit his
working-class constituents.
When Jaurès
lost his Parliamentary seat in 1889, he returned to Toulouse
as a confirmed ally of labor. Alongside his involvement with
local unions, he returned to teaching philosophy; he also
served on the Toulouse city council, composed frequent
articles for a journal of republican thought, and wrote the
two theses—one in French and one in Latin—that would qualify
him for a doctorate from the Sorbonne. His decision to take
the side of the labor movement had consequences, and he now
began to think them through. The philosophers of the
Enlightenment and the authors of the Declaration of the
Rights of Man and of the Citizen had convinced him that
politics must be founded on the dignity and freedom of the
individual person, of every individual person. He was a
universalist, a humanist, a republican. He had taught his
students at Albi that Immanuel Kant was “right to make
disinterestedness the precondition of morality and to not
subordinate man to a material and egoistic end like
interest, one’s own happiness, or even a certain particular
ideal of perfection.” Organized workers, however, spoke the
language of conflict, disruption, and solidarity based on
common experiences, and they increasingly looked beyond
their immediate fights over wages and working conditions
toward a vision of total social transformation, a vision of
a cooperative and collective society they variously called
“communism” or “socialism”. This was Jaurès’s puzzle: How
could he reconcile universal norms and self-interested
struggles, humanism and conflict, the Republic and class
solidarity? How could he be both a liberal and a socialist?
All of
Jaurès’s work from this point on was an effort to comprehend
this tangle of commitments. His first doctoral thesis sought
to reconcile the conceptual underpinnings of Kantian
idealist liberalism and Marxist materialist socialism. He
argued that the universe was constituted as an ongoing
struggle to realize the unity of consciousness and matter.
Thus, he wrote, the “battle” to enact the moral ideal of
harmony and equality “is never won, and is never lost.” In
his second thesis, he traced the roots of German socialism
back through Hegel to Fichte, Kant, and Luther, arguing that
the French Revolution’s notion of absolute individual
liberty needed to be synthesized with the dialectical German
idea that “collectivism” could be a means to individual
freedom.
Jaurès was
elected to Parliament again in 1893 in the wake of a massive
ten-week miners’ strike in Carmaux, just north of Albi,
which galvanized the local labor movement. Jaurès had given
public support and behind-the-scenes advice to the strikers,
and this time he ran for office as a labor tribune and as a
socialist. Jaurès had confidence and fervor now. His
oratorical fire and patient pursuit of socialist unity made
him a natural leader among the fractious socialists swept
into office that year.
Jaurès’s raw
mixture of liberal and socialist ideas received its first
major test five years later. In the fall of 1894, Captain
Alfred Dreyfus, the only Jew on the French Army’s General
Staff, was arrested for espionage. He was quickly convicted
and sentenced to exile in a military trial involving forged
evidence, secret evidence, and other irregularities. Few
people paid much attention, but after the novelist Emile
Zola assailed the weak evidence against Dreyfus in his
thunderous 1898 pamphlet J’accuse, the Dreyfus Affair
became the dominant issue of the day. Persuaded of Dreyfus’s
innocence, Jaurès soon became one of the most ardent and
hard-working Dreyfusards, speaking in parliament and writing
constantly about the case.
For most
French socialists, this controversy over a bourgeois army
officer seemed to be only an internal dispute within the
ruling class. For Jaurès, who insisted that socialism was
“the supreme affirmation of individual right,” an
economistic understanding of class had to give way to
something else, however. Since Dreyfus had been wrongly
convicted, Jaurès wrote,
he is no longer
either an officer or a bourgeois: by his excess of
misfortune, he is stripped of all class character. He is no
more than humanity itself, in the most extreme state of
misery and despair that can be imagined...What a mockery to
still count him among the privileged!
Workers
organized not just because they knew their own material
interests, Jaurès argued, but because they had gained
consciousness of their rights. If socialism were to
be a movement for rights, for justice, it could not ignore
any instance of injustice—even if the victim were a
bourgeois army officer. This idea of individual rights may
have originated with bourgeois liberalism, Jaurès wrote in
his monumental Histoire Socialiste (1789-1900),
but it was a living idea, subject to new interpretations.
The “molten rush of socialism that flows from the furnace of
the [French] Revolution,” he insisted, must remain fluid:
We do not claim
to freeze human society in the economic and social formulas
that prevailed from 1789 to 1795…Too often bourgeois
democratic parties limit themselves to collecting some
fragments of cooled lava at the foot of the volcano, to
gathering a few extinguished cinders around the furnace.
For
liberalism to remain a living ideal, it must change form as
conditions change, Jaurès wrote. If the labor movement
understood itself in terms of the liberal idea of individual
rights, it could pick up the standard the bourgeoisie had
let fall, and it could infuse its own activities with moral
purpose.
Jaurès
convinced all but France’s most sectarian socialists to come
together in defense of Dreyfus. This newfound left unity,
however, crumbled quickly. In response to rumors of an
impending right-wing coup, a group of centrist and
center-left politicians—including the moderate socialist
Alexandre Millerand—formed a broad coalition government
united by little besides its members’ desire to preserve
democratic institutions. Socialists who held an orthodox
Marxist vision of uncompromising class struggle were
furious. However important the existence of the republic
might be, they complained, Millerand betrayed the working
class when he sat in the cabinet with the same moderate
republicans who had, a generation before, slaughtered the
Paris Communards.
Across
Europe, socialists fell into bitter debates about the
strategic value of electoral politics and parliamentary
reform. On the left, orthodox Marxists like Karl Kautsky in
Germany and Jules Guesde in France insisted that socialism
meant a revolutionary class struggle leading to a total
transformation of society sometime in the near future, and
that parliamentary politics could only be a tool for
bringing that revolution closer. On the right, Eduard
Bernstein wrote that “what is usually termed the final goal
of socialism is nothing to me, the movement is everything,”
and argued that socialists should look to the immediate
interests of the labor movement as their guide.
Jaurès
stepped beyond this dichotomy. The day-to-day struggle for
electoral and parliamentary victories was crucial, he
insisted, and the new willingness of socialist parties to
pursue incremental reforms was a sign of growing strength,
not of lost courage. Getting serious about reform, however,
need not mean giving up the labor movement’s radical spirit.
A reformist strategy did not require that socialists
“counsel the proletariat to settle on the capitalist earth”
and reduce “the collectivist or communist order [to] a
remote paradise of which one dreams,” Jaurès proclaimed.
Rather, the socialist paradise “could be present in
[socialists’] very existence, if they had the feeling that
each of their acts, each of their thoughts, each of their
words correspond to it, echo it, and shape future events.”
Socialists should not concern themselves with an apocalyptic
transformation in the future, but should “live always in a
socialist state of grace… working in each minute, in each
hour” to bring the socialist ideal more fully into reality.
Words like “communism” came to seem, in Jaurès’s speeches
and writings, more like regulative principles than like
institutional expectations. Socialism, for Jaurès, had come
to be a politics of radical reform. Voting rights, unions,
safeguards on civil liberties, social welfare measures,
public and secular education, international law,
worker-owned and state-owned firms could all be cobbled
together in an ongoing struggle to bring the world closer to
the ideal of universal human dignity and solidarity, and
that ideal could guide and orient disparate reformist
activities. “Class” could be the rubric for organization,
“humanity” the ethical commitment.
By 1905,
Jaurès had become the acknowledged leader of French
socialism, even though his radical reformism was a minority
view within the new unified Socialist Party. He was a
familiar and warmly admired figure throughout the movement:
his solid peasant build, his square-cut beard, the
disheveled clothing that suggested his devotion to the work
of the movement and his disregard for personal glory, were
as well known as his soaring and elaborate oratory. At no
time did that oratory reach greater heights than in October
1912, as the Balkans erupted into war and the prospect of a
Europe-wide Great War loomed large, when Jaurès took the
rostrum at an international conference of socialists in
Basel, Switzerland. “In the sound of the church bells that
welcomed us, I heard a call to reconciliation,” he
proclaimed.
It reminded me
of the epigraph which Schiller placed at the beginning of
his beautiful Song of the Bell: “Vivos voco, mortuos
plango, fulgura frango…Vivos voco… I call the living to
defend life against the monster that appears on the horizon!
Mortuos plango...I mourn the innumerable dead laid
low in the east, from whom a stench arrives to torment us.
Fulgura frango…I will smash the thunderbolts of war
even as they roil the stormclouds!
Since the
French Socialist Party’s unification, Jaurès had been
concerned above all with preventing war. If workers’ class
interests could found a politics of universal human rights,
he reasoned, perhaps citizens’ patriotic feelings could be
harnessed to the principle of international solidarity.
Jaurès rejected the argument that socialists’ commitment to
international solidarity meant they had to be
anti-patriotic. Patriotism, he argued, need not mean blind
nationalism; it could mean a commitment to universalistic
liberal and socialist principles, coupled with a realization
that these principles could be enacted only within
particular states. “The nation, and the nation alone,” he
wrote, “can enfranchise all the citizens. Only the nation
can furnish the means of free development to all.” Love for
one’s own country, then, could mean love for that country’s
potential to realize the human dream of freedom and
equality. Patriotic attachments could serve as an
“apprenticeship in collective life and in a broad humanistic
sensibility.”
Jaurès held
great hopes for the educative potential of this cosmopolitan
patriotism, but he insisted that in order for those hopes to
be realized, republics would need to become more
egalitarian, more inclusive, and more deeply democratic. In
1911, he published L’Armée Nouvelle, a detailed
proposal for a “new army” in which decentralized militias
would replace standing armies and in which the officer corps
would be opened to working-class candidates. Shorn of its
elitist leadership structure and re-shaped to fit a purely
defensive military strategy, conscious of itself as an
extension of the citizenry rather than as a distinct caste
with its own interests, the new army would institutionalize
Jaurès’s cosmopolitan patriotism.
At the same
time that he called on socialists to reconsider the value of
patriotism, Jaurès took a bolder anti-war stand than did
orthodox Marxists like Guesde. For Guesde and his allies,
war was inevitable as long as capitalism remained, and
active opposition to war was futile. Jaurès rejected this
determinism. Capitalism and imperialism might tend to
foster war, he argued, but specific wars could be averted
through diplomacy or, if need be, through direct action by
the labor movement. Thus, Jaurès argued forcefully that in
the event of an aggressive war, socialists should call for a
general strike. His stand was seen as traitorous radicalism
by the Right and as naïve reformism by the Marxists. In the
last weeks of his life Jaurès worked feverishly, attending
peace conferences, addressing public rallies, and using his
significant sway within the center-left governing coalition
to push for more strenuous diplomatic efforts. War came
anyway.
Failure marked Jaurès’s last years. The French Socialist
Party achieved unity by marginalizing his conception of
radical reform; his cosmopolitan patriotism proved no match
for nationalism and militarism; his pacifism inspired his
assassination. Many of his contemporaries rejected his
liberal socialism because they found it insufficiently
optimistic, out of tune with their certainty that history
was on the side of human hopes. After the traumas of the
twentieth century, however, we cannot share their
teleological confidence. History no longer appears to be on
the side of humanity, but human dignity can still be an
ethical norm—something we pursue because it is right,
whether or not it is written into history. When he refused
to relegate socialism to the status of a future paradise,
when he insisted that the ideal of justice be brought into
tension with the practical necessities of political
mobilization in the present, Jaurès spoke to our situation.
Jaurès proposed that hope for human dignity in the modern
world depends on whether the liberal idea of individual
rights can be linked with the Marxist appreciation for
social movements and political conflict, whether the liberal
ideal can be extended to encompass a critique of the
injustices we experience in day-to-day life, whether “class”
can be understood as a mode of solidarity bringing together
all people who experience injustice, and whether immediate
attachments—whether to fellow workers or to fellow
citizens—can become an “apprenticeship” in “a broad
humanistic sensibility.” Socialism, as Jaurès understood it,
finds a comrade in every person who seeks a world where no
human being is treated merely as a means to an end. The
battle to realize that world has certainly not been won;
Jaurès reminds us that it has not been lost, either.
|