Islam
can be doubly
associated with the spirit of the Enlightenment. Long
before, as early as the middle of the eighth century, it
produced the premises of the Enlightenment; afterwards,
starting in the nineteenth century, it experienced its
effects.
Between 750
and 1050, authors made use of a surprising freedom of
thinking in their approach to religions and to the
phenomenon of belief. In their analyses, they bowed to
the
primacy of reason, honoring one of the basic
principles of the Enlightenment. This phenomenon took
place during a period of effervescence, of intense
intellectual exchange, that Islam experienced a little
more than a century after its advent, when its followers
were seeking to develop a tradition capable of
confronting much more sophisticated systems of thought.
This was also a time when newcomers to Islam continued
to remember theological systems and questions raised by
the beliefs that had seen them come into being or evolve
(like Judaism, various Christian sects, Manicheism, or
Zoroastrianism).
Ibn al-Muqaffa’
(720-756) was the first of these thinkers. Iranian by
birth, and still influenced by the Mazdean and Manichean
traditions, he was one of the first to create Arabic
literary prose, especially by adapting, in his Kalila
wa Dimna [Kalila and Dimna], a Pahlavi version of
the Indian fables going back to the Panchatantra
[Five Discourses] and the Tantrakhyayka. In his
introduction as Persian translator to this collection,
Ibn al-Muqaffa’ criticizes religions and praises
reason. For him, morality is independent of belief, and
the mulhid[i]
can be virtuous. Despite their multiplicity and their
disagreements, all faiths have three kinds of
followers: those who inherited their faith from their
father; those who were forced to believe; and those who
adhere to a religion in order to satisfy their worldly
ambitions. Furthermore, Ibn al-Muqaffa’ notes that few
people are capable of justifying their belief. After
this criticism, our author reins himself in and accepts
the minimum about which different beliefs agree, which
is reduced to moral principles hovering around negative
virtues (“do not kill, do not lie, do not speak ill of
others, do not deceive, do not steal…”), stipulations
that announce the ethical strategy of an Enlightenment
philosopher like Kant with his “postulates of practical
reason.”[ii]
In another
book, The Epistle on Friendship, Ibn al-Muqaffa’
addresses the caliph on the subject of politics. He
suggests that the cleric must submit to the prince: the
law must be taken away from the religious sphere and be
under the control of political power, but, since it is
impossible to reduce religion, it should be subordinated
to the authority of the prince. Several orientalists,
including Goitein and Gabrieli, thought that if Ibn al-Muqaffa’
had been followed on this point, Islam would have
experienced an early secularization that would have
spared it the traps in which it continues to this day to
get caught. With Ibn al-Muqaffa’, we discover the same
premises of the great Western problematic that
crystallized around dual authority, the prince and the
pontiff. To ponder such a duality would constitute the
great philosophical design that would lead the West to
the Enlightenment, passing through many stages,
including Dante’s On Monarchy (1304) and Spinoza’s
Tractatus Theologico-Politicus (1670), as well as
Hobbes’s Leviathan (1651). Despite the
difference in context, issues, and aims, following the
example of Ibn al-Muqaffa’, all of these thinkers create
a hierarchy of these two powers: either they call for
the autonomy of both the temporal and the spiritual, or
else they make the latter subordinate to the former. I
do not think the actual force of Ibn al-Muqaffa’s
propositions should be slighted by linking them to power
as it was exercised in the Persian Empire, where
religion and royalty were concentrated in one single
person.
Ibn al-Muqaffa’
also carried on a radical critique of the Koran, and
fragments of his work have reached us through the
refutation of it by a nineteenth-century author. First
of all, al-Muqaffa’ quotes a number of Koranic examples
that can be conceived of by neither reason nor
intuition. He then declares that the anthropomorphisms
applied to God contradict his invisibility and his
mystery. He goes on to insist on the imposture of the
prophets, one of the demonstrations of which is the
overzealous battle of the founder of Islam to conquer
the earthly kingdom. Finally he undertakes a critique
of monotheism in general, which cannot escape dualism,
because of the question of evil and of its presence in
the world and inside men.
Later on,
Baghdad in the ninth century saw, from its very
beginning, the emergence of the Mu’tazila [‘those
who withdraw themselves’], theologians who spread the
light of reason. Returning God to his transcendence,
they withdrew Him from the world, so to speak, and the
earthly sojourn was returned to the responsibility of
man, who was supposed to confront evil by using his free
will. But this movement distanced itself from the
spirit of the Enlightenment by allying itself with the
power of the caliph, who declared their doctrine the
ideology the State sought to impose by the constraint
and violence of an inquisitorial institution appointed
to pursue contradictors and convert them.
The era
remained open, however, to discussions and exchange
between supporters of diverse beliefs. Among the great
minds of that era, we will note the Christian Hunayn Ibn
Ishaq (808-873) who played a major role as a transmitter
of the Greek scientific and philosophical corpus. This
multidisciplinary, polyglot intellectual, familiar with
three cultures (Syriac, Greek, Arabic), well-informed
about two others (Persian, Indian), reminds us of the
great European figures of the Renaissance, the
intermediary sequence that would lead to the
Enlightenment: wasn’t he comparable to Erasmus? In one
of his books, transcending his own faith, freeing
himself from apologetics and polemics, using the
instrument of logic, he seeks to understand how truth
can be grasped in religions, and how error is introduced
and then imposed on the believer.
We will also
note, among these first “freethinkers,”[iii]
Abu ‘Isa al-Warraq (died circa 861), who criticized his
own religion (Islam) and all the others, revealing their
contradictions and their implausibilities after passing
them through the sieve of reason to end up finally at a
logical monotheism that goes beyond established beliefs
and cannot be authenticated by them. This critical
approach to established religions places its author in
surprising proximity to the Deism of the Enlightenment.
Many other
authors bear witness to a like judgment that is
critical, if not marked by skepticism. But undoubtedly
it is Abu Bakr Al-Razi (circa 854-circa 925) who seems
closest to the spirit of the Enlightenment. He was a
famous doctor and philosopher, known in the
Latin-speaking world by the name of Rhazes. In a
controversy with another Razi (Abu Hatim ar-Razi, a
Shiite theologian and an Ismaili preacher), one of the
most famous debates ever produced in the Islamic
theater, our doctor-philosopher asserts that, in order
to acquire knowledge, divine gift and reason suffice;
there is no need to believe in a particular Revelation,
bearer of discords, disputes, and wars. In the best
case, prophets are impostors, agitated sick men.
Ordinary humans do not need to be guided by a divine
law. They can think on their own, inspired by their
theoretical and practical intelligence. Razi asserts
that the philosophical horizon can only be darkened by a
belief founded on superstitions, legends, and
contradictions, to which ignorance compounded with
dogmatism is added. He also criticizes ritualism, which
creates maniacal beings obsessed with imaginary
impurities. He thinks that he himself is worth much
more than religious men: as a doctor and a man of
science, doesn’t he render an outstanding service to
humanity by relieving his fellows of the evils and
sufferings that overwhelm them when they are eaten away
by disease? He was a man who believed positively in
progress; convinced of having improved the knowledge he
inherited from Galen, he was certain that the scholars
and practitioners who followed him would in their turn
improve the science and knowledge he bequeathed to
them. He also thought that scientific truth is
provisional, endlessly evolving, destined to be
perfectible.
We would be
right to wonder why this chain of critical thought was
interrupted, why it did not have the necessary
continuators who could have led it to have an effect on
common ideas, in the realm of political realization, and
why this precocious foreshadowing of the forerunners of
the Renaissance and the Enlightenment remained
futureless, without any practical realization in
society, and without transforming collective
imaginations.
Not that the
intersection of ideas didn’t have ideological effects or
didn’t result in political events. Still, very often,
theological controversy experienced only two
paradigmatic types of political effect: one destined to
legitimize the seizure of power by one or another of the
competing parties (as in the beginning of Islam in the
opposition between the Umayyads and the ‘Alids, between
Sunnites and Shiites); and the one (analyzed by Ibn
Khaldun, 1332-1406), that repeatedly sought to establish
a purifying reform in order to reestablish power
according to the vision people had of its prophetic
origin (as illustrated by the Almoravids and the
Almohads in the eleventh and twelfth centuries in the
Muslim West). That seems to be the historical structure
where the link between thought and State, between
ideology and power, theology and politics, can be found.
Considerable
historical importance should also be attributed to the
defeat of the Mu’tazila in the middle of the
ninth century, some forty years after their triumph;
their expulsion from the heart of the State occurred
with an Inquisitorial violence that was just as radical
and ferocious as the violence they had cause to exercise
at the time of their hegemony. And their theories,
which could have been precious for the evolution of
Islam, were defeated forever. In fact, the theory of
the “created Koran” could have taken part in a process
that relativizes the sacrality of the Law and makes it
less untouchable; and their theses on freewill, choice,
and human responsibility faced with evil, could have led
the follower of Islam to become acclimated to those key
notions of modernity, freedom and the individual, which
have been erased from his mental horizon.
It is through
this episode that we see the absence of a notion of
freedom in the social and political sense, that we
observe the failure to emerge of any rudiments that
might lead to the crystallization of the notion of the
individual. The praise of reason, or its triumph over
dogma, did not take notice of the warning signs of the
problems to come.
One quality
deserves to be recalled, which is probably at the source
of these early tentative impulses: tolerance, that
other Enlightenment notion. Islam recognizes a place
for other monotheistic beliefs based on Revelation (the
Jews, the Christians and the enigmatic Sabians, who have
been linked to the Neo-Platonics, the Zoroastrians, or
the followers of the Buddha). This disposition, along
with some other Koranic principles (like the verse that
says, “No constraint in religion,” II, 256), encouraged
the liberal tendency to self-expression and, in the
atmosphere of cosmopolitan Baghdad (ninth-tenth
centuries), to arrange conferences for theological
debates where followers of the various sects could
exhibit their points of view without being harassed; in
fact the Manicheans were very active in this kind of
debate. It was especially through this sort of
“disputation,” and through the literary genre that
emerged from them, that testimonies have reached us
concerning the critical and rational approach to
religion and to the phenomenon of belief.
This
tolerance in Islam, relative as it may be, was in fact
pointed out in the famous essays that discuss it in the
Age of Enlightenment: both Locke and Voltaire perceived
in it a lesser evil compared to the triumphalist
exclusivism they were familiar with, which made no place
in the afterlife for members of other sects even though
they shared one’s evangelical beliefs.
Moreover,
during the first four centuries after the Hegira, Islam,
as it was developing, was marked by the dynamism such a
phase requires. It was in the process of constructing
itself as a religion, a theology, a culture, a
civilization. It did so in the effervescence of
exchange with and adaptation to the many traditions that
preceded it and that had produced a profound body of
work. This time of ingestion, assimilation, and
enrichment could only be open. It was starting in the
fifth century of the Hegira (eleventh century) that the
tendency to rigidity began to triumph. At that time,
all work on the Koran stopped; its definitive form was
adopted. From that decision onward, the competing
recensions and textual variants, which had given rise to
heated debates – the very ones that the modern
historical sciences are now trying to reconstitute and
reopen – were blocked out.
At that time
too, the notion of innovation (bid’a) became
tainted with a paralyzing negativity, so much so that,
to translate the word, Orientalists added a pejorative
adjective to it (“blameworthy innovation”). This
notion, however, had been necessary to legitimize the
adoption of new things that had been discovered via
contact with other civilizations that were complex in
different ways, much more developed in various areas
compared with the restrained archaism of Medina. It is
as if they thought that whatever had already been
constructed was adequate. So the effort of theological
construction was replaced by the rigor of orthopraxis,
of control and conformity to the rules of worship, as an
identitarian reference-point subject to social censure.
In this
context, vast syntheses would be composed,
combining theology, mysticism, and philosophy,
elaborating on practical morality, a kind of how-to-live
based on the primacy of the religious, syntheses that
seem definitive. The most eloquent of these is the one
by Abu Hamid Ghazali (1058-1111), Ihya’ ‘ulum ad-Din
(The Revival of the Religious Sciences).
It is as if
the literate members of Islam thought that their edifice
was complete, that it had reached an unparalleled
perfection, and that it was appropriate ever after to
fix it in place and conserve it, to preserve its memory,
remote from any dynamic or change. Hence the profusion,
starting with that era, of encyclopedias and
dictionaries concerning all the fields of knowledge.
But the worst
was yet to come, at the end of the thirteenth century,
with the Hanbali scholar Ibn Taymiyya (died 1328), who
would radicalize even more the notion of bid’a,
whose noxious presence he would index, all the way up to
the already restrictive syntheses of the eleventh
century. He never stopped hunting for what he
considered intruders into the original home: he would
denounce the introduction of Jewish, Christian, Greek,
Manichean, Mazdean, and Hindu motifs in constructs that
ought to have been induced only by the Koran alone. He
would lambaste the echoes of philosophy (Greek),
of mysticism (Christian, Hindu), of the worship of
saints (polytheist), of visiting graves (pagan) – so
many borrowings that, according to him, disfigure the
original building. This author would produce the
pattern from which all future fundamentalism would
derive; he was a sworn enemy of the Enlightenment, of
its premises and its effects on Islam.
The
Enlightenment as a movement of ideas was introduced into
the land of Islam after Napoleon’s expedition to Egypt
(1798), which provoked something like electroshock in
the Arab Orient. Islam had thought itself superior till
then, or at least equal to Europe in military force,
comforts, and the conditions of life produced by the
achievement of civilization. But now it suddenly found
itself confronted with arms, material goods, technical
methods, and scientific approaches that were unknown and
in some ways more efficient. So it wanted to understand
the reasons for European advancement, for such progress
that made it aware of its own historical lagging and,
above all, of the balance of power that had reduced it
to being in a weaker position, fated to be subjugated.
Having reached this awareness, Muslim scholars, in their
various Arabic, Turkish, Persian, Asiatic spheres, would
discover the Enlightenment and its principles.
Travelers from these various regions visited the
European metropolises and communicated their fascination
to their compatriots and coreligionists. A veritable
movement of Occidentalism, or even of Occidentalophilia,
arose among the elite of these countries. A longing for
Europe was expressed in the policies of the various
governments, whether through the reforms of the
tanzimet introduced in the Ottoman Empire by the
sultans Mahmud II (reigned 1808-1839) and Abdulmejid I
(reigned 1839-1861) or in the framework of the
modernization of Egypt under the initiative of Mohammed
Ali (1805-1849). The new problematic of the
Enlightenment was then perceived in connection with the
analogies or premises that the Islamic tradition might
offer. Thus, the deism and tolerance preached by the
new Europe encountered an echo in Akbarism, which shaped
the Ottoman, Arabic, and Persian elite. Akbarism was
the metaphysical and moral theory taken from texts
written by the Andalusian theosophist Ibn Arabi
(1165-1240), who spread his concept of the oneness
of Being, and who redirected Islamic belief towards
an immanentist form of deism coupled with religious
relativism, making Koranic relativism even more
systematic, going so far as to grant credit and a share
of truth to all forms of belief, even the most pagan
ones. A European during the Age of Enlightenment, Lady
Mary Wortley Montagu, wife of the English ambassador to
Constantinople (1717), witnessed the effect of these
ideas on the Ottoman elite, for whom non-Islamic beliefs
were intelligible, understandable, visitable, likeable.
What’s more, the closeness of this “deism” to the
philosophy of Spinoza (who was at the source of the
deism of the Enlightenment and of Romanticism) helped a
number of these enlightened Muslims to receive the
Masonic message and to join some of its lodges, like
Amir Abdelkader (1807-1883), disciple of his medieval
master Ibn Arabi, whose interpretation he put into
practice, before joining Freemasonry.
Moreover,
faced with the challenge of adapting to the European
novelties engendered by the Age of Enlightenment, Muslim
theologians restored the primacy of reason, like
Muhammad ‘Abduh (1848-1905), the Egyptian Mufti, who
wrote “that in case of conflict between reason and
tradition, it is reason that has the right to decide.”
They had recourse to the notion of bid’a
(innovation) to restore Islam’s original positivity.
With its help, the adoption by the Ottomans of the
constitutional principle was legitimized. This notion
was also combined with that of maslaha, an
adaptation in the tenth century by the western Malakite
school of the utilitas publica, taking into
account the shared interest in the application of law,
correcting the rules when it has been proven that the
interest of the community calls for it (echoing the
corrigere jus propter utilitatem publicam upheld by
Roman law). In this traditional perspective, Zurqani, a
theologian in Cairo, proclaimed, in 1710, the necessity
of taking new measures with the appearance of new
events: “One should not think it strange that laws be
adapted to circumstances.”[iv]
Muhammad
‘Abduh and his disciples had recourse to these notions
(bid’a, maslaha) to adopt the principles of the
Enlightenment and to lead in its name political activity
against both local despotism and the colonial aims of
Europe. On this point precisely, they spotted a lack of
agreement between principles and deeds in the behavior
of European humanity. Such an argument was notably
invoked in 1834, just four years after the Algiers
expedition, in the first Francophone book that came out
of the Maghreb, Le Miroir [The Mirror], in which
the author, Hamdan Khodja,[v]
notes in his preface how the French, by invading
Algeria, were attacking the principles of 1789 and were
inconsistent, since here, in Africa, they make destitute
a people, a nation, and a State that were already fully
constituted, while there, in Europe, they defend
peoples, nations, and States that are still in the
process of being established (like Greece, Poland, and
Belgium). We have elsewhere called this dishonoring of
principle through action “the test of the universal”
that “the Western aporia” confronts.[vi]
We can
distinguish three sequences in which the effects of the
Enlightenment are imprinted in the wake of a heritage
that tends to be closely linked with Muhammad ‘Abduh.
First of all, Qasim Amin touched on the symptomatic
question of women in two pamphlets, published in 1898
and 1900, where he proclaims loudly and clearly the
equality of women, their liberation, their emergence
from the gynaeceum, and calls for the establishment of a
mixed society, for the participation of women in
education, in the spread of knowledge, and in
production: the modernization of women, he said,
requires their unveiling, their enjoyment of freedom and
equality. Such claims can also be illumined by a
positive vision of bid’a (innovation) and of
maslaha, that principle of public interest, which
would be appropriate for an Islam freed of the letter so
that the spirit can be found in it.
Then, Sheikh
Ali Abderraziq (1888-1966) published in 1925 his essay
L’Islam et les fondements du pouvoir (Islam and
the Foundations of Power).[vii]
Here, the author demonstrates that the notion of an
Islamic State has never existed. He notes that the
Caliphate, at the time of its greatness, under the
Umayyads as well as under the Abbassids, did not produce
a new form of government; it simply adopted the imperial
structures of Byzantium and then of Persia, both of
which had proven their administrative and military
efficacy. Thus contemporary Muslims should construct
their State by drawing inspiration from the best
examples that other nations have produced; they should
therefore construct a State, inspired by the Western
example created by the Enlightenment. Abderraziq
emphasizes moreover that what matters in the prophetic
experience of Mohammed is spiritual and moral direction
much more than giving military or royal examples; for
him, Islam is a divine message, not a system of
government; a religion, not a State. And he ends by
recommending a radical separation between the spiritual
and temporal in order to re-found the State and
reconstruct law according to the requirements of
modernity.
Finally, Taha
Hussein (1889-1973) would intrude on the period between
the two wars with his Western, positivist message,
genealogically linked with the Enlightenment. It is
Hussein who would draw the consequences of historical
literary criticism so far as to perceive a
legitimization and a posteriori authentication of the
language and myths of the Koran in the creation of the
collection of early Arabic poetry, whose roots in
pre-Islamic times he considers in context. Moreover,
Taha Hussein reminds his compatriots of the place of
Egypt, and Alexandria, in the formation of Greek culture
during one of its final phases, as well as the role of
that same culture in the formation of Arabic classicism,
a twofold reason that restores to Arab identity sources
that it shares with the West. This sharing of roots
legitimizes participation in the values of the modern,
which is of an obvious European genesis, especially in
the framework of the spaces opened by the Enlightenment
philosophers.
However, we
still have to discover why these undeniable effects of
the Enlightenment did not propel Islam towards a
decisive, almost irrevocable mutation.[viii]
The present state of these countries makes it evident
that the effect of the Enlightenment was not only
insufficient but frankly disappointing. Despotism,
fanaticism, superstition, obscurantism, economic
poverty, under-development, absence of an internalized
social contract: that is the diagnosis that keeps the
countries of Islam far from the lessons of the
Enlightenment. I will suggest at least three reasons
for what has ended up being thought of as a failure.
First of all,
the policy of modernization that had begun in the
beginning of the nineteenth century failed. Here it is
a question of a modernization determined by the
assimilation of Technology, the same standard by which
Japanese success is measured when it came to expression
through the military victory over Russia in 1905. This
event fascinated Islam, since it revealed that
Technology of Western origin can be mastered by an
Eastern country on its own, through loyalty to itself
alone. However, this loyalty to self, not subject to
the principles of the Enlightenment, led successful
Japan towards militarist and fascist nationalism, even
if the Meiji era might have been etymologically linked
to the notion of light, a term whose use as trope and
metaphor grants it an ambivalent, if not suspicious,
polysemy.[ix]
Though the emergence of Technology is historically
associated with the emergence of the Enlightenment, we
should be aware of its autonomy, obvious in the Japanese
example, as well as in the use to which it was put for
barbaric purposes during the European twentieth
century. But at the same time it is difficult to
conceive of the Enlightenment taking root in a society
that drew no advantages from the comfort and material
wealth that Technology brought with it. It is
necessary, then, to the advent of the Enlightenment, but
it is autonomous from it. And the defeat of the
Enlightenment can be seen as much in Japan’s success as
in Islam’s failure in assimilating Technology.
I associate
this failure of the Enlightenment with the fear of
radical thinking that urges separation and rupture. The
ideas and principles of the Enlightenment emerged by
opposing tradition, by refuting it, by disengaging from
it. This is a phenomenon that was not conceived to
accord with the legacy of religion, or even to
accommodate itself to it. The reformers and reformists
of Islam did not risk the adventure of treason;
timorous, they were limited by obsession with fidelity
to their creed, which was not confined in a separate
space, which might have trembled in the unassailable
secret of the heart; it is as if they were afraid of
becoming divided subjects, accepting their own
dividedness.
Finally,
added to this is the emergence, at the end of the
1920’s, of anti-Westernism as a combative ideology
developed by Islamic fundamentalists, who revived all
the traditional rejections, which they radicalized even
more, drawing support especially from Ibn Taymiyya, and
through hunting down all foreign influence, which was
supposed to contaminate original purity. They returned
to the denunciation of the bida’, innovations
understood in the most pejorative way, as it had been
over-determined in its negativity in the eighteenth
century by Ibn ‘Abd al-Wahhab, the founder of Wahhabism,
whose proselytizing aggression would become worldwide
with the influx of petrodollars into Saudi Arabia after
the oil shock of 1973, entering an Islamic domain that
had been vacant since the defeat of various forms of
postcolonial populism.
Faced with
the ebbing away of the Enlightenment, I would like to
insist on the role that Europe can play in its
reactivation. I mentioned earlier that Western gap
between the principles of the Enlightenment and the
actions that ruined its universal dissemination. But
the European individual, in these last few decades of
peace, of work on self, of ethical vigilance, seems at
last capable of producing deeds that are in keeping with
his principles. I know that this good example is
difficult to maintain in practice, especially when it is
not easy to detach it from positions that distinguish
between dominant and dominated, strong and weak, rich
and poor. But it would still be tempting to put to the
test such an exemplariness to the limits of the possible
and the reasonable by committing ourselves to the
principle of justice. Enacting it, the opportunity to
reestablish the luster of the Enlightenment would be
offered to us, and to give it back a universal credit
that would help to revive its home in Islam, by
supporting those who, in its heart, wish to live to
their final consequences the divisions that have always
agitated it, in this war of hierarchical structures, of
authorities and interpretations, an incessant civil war
one of the stakes of which is still winning the
knowledge of the Enlightenment in a context of
separation and rupture.
Notes
[i]
The term means “one who deviates from the
straight line,” and designates, from the ninth
century on, an atheist.
[ii]
Dominique Urvoy, Les Penseurs libres dans
l’Islam classique [Freethinkers in classical
Islam], Paris: Albin Michel, 1996, p. 40.
[iii]
As Dominique Urvoy likes to call them.
[iv]
Quoted by Ignaz Goldziher, Le Dogme et la loi
en Islam, Paris: L’éclat/Geuthner, 2005, p.
217. In English: Introduction to Islamic
Theology and Law, Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1981.
[v]
Hamdan Khodja, Le Miroir, Paris: Sindbad,
1985, pp. 37-38.
[vi]
Abdelwahab Meddeb, Dédale, No. 5-6,
Postcolonialisme, Paris: Maisonneuve &
Larose, Spring 1997, p. 12.
[vii]
Translated into French from Arabic by Abdou
Filali-Ansary, Paris: La Découverte, 1994.
[viii]
I say “almost irrevocable” to temper an absolute
judgment and to remind us what experience has
taught us, namely that no experience is
definitive: the Enlightenment is not
safeguarded on the very soil that saw its birth;
it did not keep Europe from plunging into the
darkness of the twentieth century (with
totalitarianisms, National Socialism, and
Stalinism).
[ix]
We can testify to the use of this term in
ancient times, in quite different metaphysical
and religious horizons, far from secular
reason: the fire cult established by Zoroaster,
the Platonic duality of the brilliance of Ideas
and the penumbra of the cave, the Manichean
duality of the good associated with day and evil
linked to night, resurgence of the metaphysics
of the Ishraq, illuminism reinvented by
Sohrawardi (1155-1191), which combines the
metaphors of Zoroaster, Plato, and Mani with the
verse on Light (“Light on light...,” Koran,
XXIV, 35), to locate the gleam of dawn in the
original East towards which the soul returns, in
comparison with the West of the ending, prison
of the body, condition of our sojourn here
below.
*Translated
by Charlotte Mandell