Wayward Comments
On the 12th September
2006, a day not very far from a date etched into
many of our memories, the current Pope, Benedict
XVI, gave a speech in Germany. This speech had many
Muslims in uproar, and left many others questioning
the Catholic Church’s official approach to Islam,
religious tolerance and inter-faith communication
more generally. The controversy was such that the
Pope was obliged to offer points of clarification
and something close to an apology.
In giving a speech within the
context of a German university, Pope Benedict
addressed generally the topic of the relation
between ‘faith and reason’ and introduced this theme
by recounting a dialogue between a Medieval
Byzantine Emperor, Manuel II and a so-called
“Persian interlocutor”.
As a spokesperson for the Pope has subsequently
claimed, the Pope had used the reading of this
dialogue as a means of reflecting in an “academic
context” upon the theme of the “relationship between
religion and violence in general”, with the
conclusion of a “clear and radical rejection of the
religious motivation of violence, from whatever side
it may come”.
We might reserve our judgment upon the Pope’s
purpose for recounting this dialogue, whether it was
academic, strategic or otherwise, and consider for
the moment the content of the now notorious dialogue
as recounted by the Pope.
Pope Benedict recounts a moment
in the seventh conversation which touches upon the
theme of ‘holy war’. The Pope notes that the
Byzantine Emperor Manuel II addresses his Persian
interlocutor with “startling brusqueness” on the
central question of the relation between religion
and violence in general. The Emperor says: “Show me
just what Mohammed brought that was new, and there
you will find things only evil and inhuman, such as
his command to spread by the sword the faith he
preached”. Pope Benedict argues that Emperor Manuel,
after having expressed himself so forcefully, goes
on to explain in detail the reasons why spreading
the faith through violence is something
unreasonable. This involves the argument that
violence is incompatible with the nature of God and
the nature of the soul. “God”, Emperor Manuel says:
(I)s not pleased by blood – and
not acting reasonably is contrary to God’s nature.
Faith is born of the soul, not the body. Whoever
would lead someone to faith needs the ability to
speak well and to reason properly, without violence
and threats … To convince a reasonable soul, one
does not need a strong arm or weapons of any kind,
or any other means of threatening a person with
death.
Pope Benedict goes on to claim
that the decisive statement in this argument against
violent conversion is that: “not to act in
accordance with reason is contrary to God’s nature”.
To which, drawing upon the modern editor of the
dialogue (Theodore Khoury), he suggests, is
self-evident to the Byzantine Emperor influenced by
Greek philosophy, but this however, is not
apparently so evident to what the Pope refers to as,
“Muslim teaching” – of which he claims contains the
conception that “God is absolutely transcendent” and
therefore, not bound up with human categories, or
even that of rationality.
For Pope Benedict, this supposed
distinction is key, and the rest of his lecture is
an extrapolation of a relationship shared between
Greek philosophy and Christian thinking – the
equating of God’s nature with the logos. Pope
Benedict quotes approvingly then, the line in the
Gospel of John (1:1) – ‘In the beginning was the
logos’ – noting that here the logos is
for us not simply the ‘word’, but also, ‘reason’.
For Benedict then, Christian faith and reason are
intertwined. His quotation of Emperor Manuell II is
to affirm the argument that religious faith begins
with and is to be spread by, reason, and not by
violence – that is, by reasoning, communication,
enlightenment, and by love.
Yet, while this line sounds at
first convincing, or at least appeals to the ear,
there is something more, something amiss here,
something is rotten in this account, something
stinks. At a surface level there involves a
particular historical hypocrisy. This is perhaps bad
enough, but there is something more, something about
the all too neat division between reason, on the one
hand, and violence on the other, which I find
unsettling and which gives ground for further
investigation.
Misunderstanding and Hypocrisy
What might initially be amiss
within the Pope’s comments? While the Pope does
mention one central injunction given in the
Qur’an – that “There is no compulsion in
religion” (Qur’an 2:256). He, however, still
presents a very limited, distorted and reductionist
account of Islam and gives no reference the multiple
historical traditions of Islamic thinking – or to
the continued plurality of perspectives within Islam
upon the question of the relation between the reason
and divine.
One element that is troubling
about the Pope’s depiction of Islam is the manner in
which he sets up a dichotomy containing Greek
philosophy, Christianity and the logos on the
one side, and Islam on the other. The Pope takes one
particular account given by a Muslim thinker – Ibn
Hazn – that God is absolutely transcendent, beyond
our categories, beyond rationality – and portrays
the whole of Islam as adopting this position. Such a
move is erroneous, naïve and in bad faith. It is
akin to one pointing to a particular Christian
thinker, say Origen, or Joseph Smith Jr.(the founder
of the Mormons), and claiming that either of their
accounts of the relation between reason and the
divine are representative of the whole of Christian
thinking. No decent Christian theologian would make
such a blatant error in ignoring the plurality of
theological conceptions within their own tradition
of thinking, so why should it be okay to speak in
such a manner about another faith?
Through building such a sharp
dichotomy between the logos or reason,
apparently shared by Greek philosophy and
Christianity but not by what the Pope ambiguously
calls “Muslim teaching”, Pope Benedict erases,
silences, distorts and suppresses at least 500 years
of Islamic thought which engaged with and developed
the notion of the logos of post-Socratic
Greek philosophy. Major figures of the Islamic
enlightenment, Ibn Sina (Avicenna) and Ibn Rushd
(Averroes), not to mention the Jewish philosopher
Moses Maimonides, are completed ignored by the
Pope’s account. These philosophers, who were also
men of deep faith, and the many others who preceded
and followed them, (including Muslim philosophers of
the present) thought through precisely this question
discussed by the Pope – the relation between God and
the logos, between the divine and reason.
While many of these thinkers have been marginalised
by mainstream Islam, their historical importance
should not be forgotten, and there is good reason to
re-emphasise their teachings in response to
dogmatism and religious fundamentalism.
Such figures are also
historically important to Medieval Christianity’s
re-engagement with Greek philosophy which took place
through the mediation of Islamic scholarship and via
a critical reflection upon the relationship between
reason and the divine, laid out by the scholars of
the Islamic enlightenment. The cross-over of ideas
between the Islamic and Christian worlds was central
to a post-Roman Christian heritage. To not
acknowledge this, and to repress it, as Pope
Benedict has done, is to not only live within a
world of historical abstraction, but to ignore the
movement and sharing of ideas between cultures and
religions that is at the heart of modern conceptions
of Judaism, Christianity and Islam.
While the Pope’s comments are
unsettling they are not uncommon. His portrayal of
Christianity as the religion that is of the logos,
the religion of reason, is placed in sharp contrast
with his depiction of Islam as the religion which
shuns the logos, the religion of unreason,
‘the unreasonable religion’. Such a depiction, as
clearly pointed out by Edward Said
over twenty years ago, has been typical of a
dominant Western, Christian attitude towards the
Islamic world which was used to justify and
legitimate the colonisation of the Middle East by
Europeans and United States Americans.
The Pope’s portrayal of Islam as the religion of
unreason follows in the footsteps of countless
Christian and secular Europeans and United States
Americans who have painted the Muslim as irrational,
stupid, unreasonable, uncivilised, violent, dirty
and so on. The Pope’s move is an old and typical
move, one which portrays the universe as cleaved
into two, reason against unreason, civilisation
against barbarism. There is an old colonial voice
emerging from the Pope’s robes, one which is
mobilised now in the climate of the so-called ‘war
on terror’ and the ever-louder calls from both
Social Democrats and Conservatives in Europe to hold
onto and affirm so-called ‘Christian values’ against
the cultural threats of non-white immigrants from
the various parts of the Islamic world.
What is perhaps most disturbing
within the Pope’s speech was his perpetuation of a
thoroughly medieval prejudice that Islam is and was
a religion ‘spread by the sword’. Now while Pope
Benedict has subsequently attempted to distance
himself from the content of his quotation of Manuel
II, the implication of using this quote without
caution, or direct criticism, perpetuates the
erroneous view that Islam is a religion spread by
violence. This is an old prejudice and while the
Pope has distanced himself from it he has not
directly refuted it. Rather, his failure to talk
about the historical violence carried out by
religious believers and to simply attribute this
violence to “cultural limitations” is a mark of
theological inadequacy and historical hypocrisy.
If Pope Benedict was to have
seriously engaged with the question of the relation
between violence and religion this would have to
begin with, I would suggest, in the least, two
points of examination. Firstly, with an analysis of
the context and rationale of any acts of violence
attributed to the prophets of Judaism, Christianity
and Islam – whether this be the throwing of the
money lenders out of the Temple in Jerusalem, or, of
the defence of Medina. Secondly, such an examination
would have to involve an honest acknowledgement of
the violence committed historically by religious
institutions and their believers. For Pope Benedict
this would necessarily have to involve an open
acknowledgment of the massive violence of the
Crusades, the re-conquest of southern Spain, the
invasion and colonisation of Central and South
America and an institutional silence within the
highest levels of the Catholic Church during the
genocide of the Jews of Europe. If the Pope was to
take the question of the relation between violence
and religion seriously, to investigate it seriously
in the name of reason, then he would have to ask
these hard questions and he would have to recognise
and face up to a large number of highly
uncomfortable historical facts.
Yet, Pope Benedict has not taken
this question seriously, he has merely engaged in an
exercise of mud slinging against the world of Islam
and has participated in the expression of European
prejudice against non-European religious belief.
This attitude is not one of inter-faith dialogue,
nor of open, unprejudiced debate in the name of
reason. Rather, the attitude, marked by prejudice
and aggression shares far too many uncomfortable
resonances with earlier Christian violent actors,
the Crusaders and Conquistadors. And while the
hypocrisy of Pope Benedict’s comments has been
infinite – the depth of his apologies has been
particularly shallow.
Violence and Reason
While holding onto these
criticisms of Pope Benedict’s comments I would like
to push on a little further into one question opened
by the Pope, that of the relation between reason,
religion and violence. The assumption made by Pope
Benedict, is one that has been echoed by many
religious and secular thinkers within recent times:
that is, violence is contrary to faith and reason.
The assumption is that violence is an exception, an
aberration, and that it is opposed to the
non-violent ethos of love within faith, and
non-violent communication or dialogue within reason.
The idea is quite beautiful, but is it a correct
representation of either faith or reason – might not
each contain degrees of violence? Or, at least,
might not an ethics of love, one which sits at the
intersection of faith and reason, contain a violence
which we too often overlook? Perhaps there is a
certain degree of violence contained within love, a
violence sitting within the intersection of faith
and reason. I call this violence the ethics of
exclusion, and aspects of this can be seen
within two prominent religious injunctions shared by
Christianity and Islam.
The injunction, ‘Thou shalt not
kill’ (Exodus 20:13), might be considered as
a general prohibition upon killing, a prohibition
against murder, a prohibition perhaps even against
violence in general. The injunction may be thought
in one sense to be an expression of an attitude
towards non-violence stemming from and attributed to
the divine, the logos or reason of the
divine, given in the quotation of Emperor Manuel,
that “God”, “is not pleased by blood – and not
acting reasonably is contrary to God’s nature”. Yet,
does this injunction involve an absolute prohibition
upon killing and violence? There are of course
multiple and conflicting answers to this question,
and I am not pretending here to offer the definitive
solution.
Yet, in thinking about this
question some comments by Augustine are relevant,
and have been highly influential over many
Christians and those who inherit Western traditions
of law and ethics influenced by aspects of
Christianity. For Augustine, the commandment against
killing is not absolute. Rather, he argues that
“divine authority itself has made certain exceptions
to the rule that it is not lawful to kill men”.
For Augustine, he who is commanded by God to kill,
such as the commandment by God to Abraham that he
kill his son, is excepted from the prohibition upon
killing. Further, those who wage wars under public
authority, or maintain peace and civil order against
crime and civil war, may kill and use violence
without acting in contradiction of the injunction
‘Thou shalt not kill’. Furthermore, for Augustine,
and for the majority of Christians, the killing of
plants and animals is exempted from this general
prohibition.
The prohibition upon killing
becomes even more complicated when considered in
light of the injunction – ‘Thou shalt love thy
neighbour as thyself’ (Matthew, 22:39). While
at first glance one would normally assume that the
notion of love has little to do with violence and
killing, a brief extrapolation of the concept shows
this not to be the case. One can quite easily think
of the notion of a political community that is
guided by an ethic of love – love as the ethic which
binds humans together and brings them closer to the
divine through the activity of ethical behaviour.
Such an ethic of love involves also notions of
protection, notions of care for the weak, the poor,
the social outcasts, the marginalised, and as such
it is a radical ethic of inclusion. And yet, such an
ethic also necessitates the defence of those
who are loved against those who may threaten or do
violence to them.
The injunction to love thy
neighbour involves the injunction to help one’s
neighbour against those who might do violence to
them. So in the situation where the neighbour is
injured by crime, love may necessitate the provision
of public order, peace and security and maybe even
punishment against those who break the civil law. In
the situation where the neighbour is attacked by an
enemy, the injunction to love might even involve
going to war to assist and defend one’s neighbour,
and in such a situation killing and violence may be
a practical and necessary outcome of the ethical
injunction to love. This is not to say that the use
of violence is necessary, in a situation of conflict
there may be other methods of defending or
safeguarding the neighbour. However, there remains a
certain potentiality for violence contained within
the concept of love and a certain aspect of its
necessity it buried deep within the normative
structure of the concept.
One way of thinking about the
ethics of exclusion, at least in its relation to
love, might be to think of it as the failure of
love. That is, love sets out an ethical demand
that we should embrace, help and care for our
neighbour. However, in practice each human
individual, or each institution, because each is
limited and finite, can only extend its love, in
space and time, to a limited and discreet set of
others. In this respect, while the demand of love
may be infinite, its practice might only be finite,
and thus, as a result of finitude, one neighbour is
left behind, left out, excluded, left to go hungry,
or left to stand at the border or outside the city
wall.
However, to split love and ethics
in this way might be to discount the exclusionary
aspect, the violent aspect of love, to push it
towards the outer boundaries of the concept of love
itself and thus to consider it as only a pragmatic
afterthought. Such an approach is politically
dangerous. One can do profound violence but justify
this after the act by claiming that violence was
done with all the good intentions of love. Too often
the violence of love is explained away, rendered
irrelevant, repressed even, by placing blame upon
the wretchedness of finite, human, earthly life.
Such an explanation is used all too commonly today
to justify the civilian causalities within war –
so-called ‘collateral damage’. Those innocents
bombed and killed by aggressive war are represented
as the failures of love, the people we tried to save
through love but killed through error.
Such a rigid dualism between the
infinite and the finite, between supposedly pure
notions of love and reason on the one hand, and the
muddied and violent operation of human practicality
on the other, is both conceptually tenuous and
ethically irresponsible. By subscribing to such a
dualism Pope Benedict is able to wash his hands of
the historical violence carried out by Christians
and the Catholic Church. For the Pope, the violence
of history seems redeemed by the pure idea, the pure
logos, and by ‘good intentions’ directed
towards such an end.
This dualism, either within
theology or within secular ethics, should be
rejected. The relation between reason, ethics and
violence is not properly understood if we think of
an ethical concept, such as love, as being pure in
theory, within a realm of pure reason, but which
subsequently becomes impure, dirtied, complicated
and violent in the move from theory to practice. The
better approach is to think about the nature of
normative demands within ethical concepts and to
think about the conflicts, or what might be called
normative contradictions, that occur within
reason, within the logos. That is, within
every ethical norm, such as love, there resides a
demand that it be realised – this demand is an
infinite demand, an infinite potentiality. Also
contained within this normative demand is the
potentiality for violence. The potentiality for
violence occurs within thought, within reason, and
can be seen to occur as soon as the norm, say love,
is directed or extended towards distinct objects. At
the level of reason, at the level of only thinking
in our heads or on paper, this violence is not yet
real physical violence; it is only yet the
potentiality for violence. Yet, this potentiality is
contained within the ethical concept itself, it is a
certain potentiality for violence contained within
the word.
A certain sense of this might be
seen to be present within a parable about the story
of the fall of Satan (Iblis) in the Qur’an
(2:34). The story goes that Satan formerly an
angel (or a jinni in other accounts) was
commanded by God to prostrate or bow down before the
newly created Adam. Satan refused to prostrate
himself before Adam and was subsequently thrown out
of heaven. The standard account is that Satan was
punished for his arrogance and for his disobedience
to God. One Sufi reinterpretation of this story is
that Satan, out of all of the angels was the only
one who followed the Islamic notion that there is
only one God. Hence, that one should only prostrate
oneself before God and one should not bow down to
idols, or set other beings near or on the level of
God. On this counter interpretation Satan attempted
to fulfil the word of God but this brought him into
contradiction with the word of God.
In part the story of Satan is
representative of the sense of normative
contradiction contained within reason, within the
logos, which as irreconcilable contains the
potentiality for violence within it. It is this
parable of Satan which paints a much clearer picture
of the relationship between reason, faith and
violence. Conflict and violence are contained within
reason – within divine reason itself. Here there is
no split world; violence is not separated off from a
pure reason by the introduction of finitude, human
arrogance, or human error as is the case of the
narrative of the fall of man through sin. Rather,
the error is already contained within reason and it
is this point we need to hold onto if we are
properly to come to terms with the relation between
reason, faith and violence.
Contemporary Relevance
So how might
the notion of the ethics of exclusion help us
think about contemporary
political questions such as the so-called ‘war on
terror’ or the West’s relationship with the multiple
worlds and traditions grouped under the broad
heading of ‘Islam’? Well, we should reject the type
of story that is becoming increasingly popular in
many circles, not just conservative, but also
liberal-democratic and social democratic, that Islam
is a religion of violence while Christianity is a
religion of non-violence. One way of rejecting this
false dichotomy is, contra Pope Benedict, to attempt
take an unbiased, empirical view of history, to
accept the violence performed by many different
religious and secular actors throughout history.
Yet, such an approach may not be
enough, because the violence of the past, whether
this be carried out by Jews, Christians, Muslims, or
by the secular modern state, is almost always
justified and legitimated after the event by many of
our ethical conceptions. That is, empirical violence
of the past is all too easily re-described,
re-legitimated, re-narrated as having ethical
legitimacy. Too often historical and contemporary
violence is portrayed as the failure of love;
painted as well-intentioned but unplanned violence,
the result of error and human limitation. The
colonial wars in Afghanistan and Iraq are often
painted this way. For many, their violence is
redeemed by love, and the answer is always to be
more ethical, to act in accordance with love,
regardless of the violence which this produces.
Instead of such a view what is
required is an effort to hold onto the violence of
love – the violence contained within reason, ethics
and the operation of normative contradiction. This
violence occurring as a potentiality should not be
separated from a pure reason, ethics or love.
Rather, these three need to be re-conceptualised by
a focus and emphasis upon the role and status of the
potentiality of violence contained within them.
Such an approach to the thinking about ethics is
needed, especially so, when attempting to come to
terms with the nature of post-secular violence
trampling upon the present.
For many on the Left, such an
engagement with the operation of religious concepts,
as I have attempted to sketch out here through the
constellation of reason, violence and love, appears
as a form of intellectual regression. However, by
taking such a stance the Left loses a field of
engagement that might otherwise be used to refute on
their own terms many of the religious arguments put
by institutional figures such as the Pope, and those
made by political figures who attempt to hold onto
the religious-moral higher ground as a means of
countering their disastrous and violent policies
within empirical-social reality. Further, by
engaging with some of the concepts and forms of
thinking characteristic of what can be termed –
post-secular reason – the Left opens itself to a
wider dialogue with members of the Islamic world who
share many of the ethical and political goals
central to the struggle against imperialist war and
global capitalism. We can take the differing
critiques of religion given by Hegel, Feuerbach and
Marx seriously, and still engage critically with the
content of religious concepts that are used to
mobilise millions of religious actors around the
world. Many on the Left are already doing this and
as long as we do not lose ourselves completely
within religious concepts the project of such an
engagement can be a productive one.