“I don’t believe in
a God that created harelips” - Peter
Sloterdijk
The
human genome has shown how close we are to
animals. Could this not lead to greater
kindness to animals?
The
deeper insight into the genetic similarity
between animals and humans and between humans
and plants leads us to a situation which many
people can understand and that was formulated
in German Idealism and in natural philosophy
around 1800. Think about Schelling who
revolted against with “the complete death blow
to all of nature” Fichtes moral idealism. Much
of what we encounter anew in the labs was
philosophically present two hundred years
ago. What was then presented in a frock coat
comes to us again in the language of the white
smock. The broad population has the right idea
that must be publicly explained about what
occurs in the technicians’ laboratory. It is
there that developments are dangled that
concern the entire human condition.
Who
can control these laboratories?
Obviously
there is a type of a Council among those
involved. Since a couple of years ago crowds
of people have been gathering around the
laboratories of the gene cardinals —a desire
that manifests itself like type of
bio-political church following of sorts. And a
second ring is forming around this nucleus of
anthropologically-engaged that is coming
together among the lawyers of the remaining
creatures. These assume a new a type of legal
representation or trust toward the steps of
animal evolution. These themselves have no
voice and represent a vulnerable life and have
a say among the full collection of living
creatures that are coming in to being because
we perceive them as vulnerable lives and as
having a delicate ecological connection.
The
animals will soon be sitting with us at the
table.
Do we
need, in addition to a code of anthropological
technologies also a code of animal
technologies?
Absolutely. I think that a new branch of
occupation will come into existence, a new
category of legal competence. In one way or
another there will be animal lawyers and
animal trusts. The traditional animal agencies
affiliated with veterinarians, agricultural
ministers and animal protection groups do not
suffice in order to create an enforceable set
of ethics that corresponds to the knowledge of
the similarities between humans and animals.
One can clearly detect this tendency from the
creative unrest that has touched upon all of
Europe for weeks with regard to the BSE
scandals and other animal-related
catastrophes. At last, people are talking
about animals again and about farmers again
too. Up until now farmers were the unrewarded
agents of the animal world in our society.
Their tasks must be newly defined and
compensated.
At
present millions of animals are being burned
to death because of BSE and foot and mouth
disease. How can one reconcile this with
respect for animals?
Animals
are allowing themselves to be remembered
through catastrophes and I am certain that
this will lead to lasting effects for their
diet and the ethos toward animals. But unlike
before one cannot delegate the question of
guilt onto society as in the times in which a
left wing radical agitation movement existed
which held that “society” was an address on
which all of the blames could be pinned. Today
we’ve learned that it doesn’t make sense to
project vague moral ills onto society.
Everyone who is able to function is
accountable. Society does not operate as a
whole. At the center of the BSE debate is not
“society” but the meat market. We cannot
achieve anything today with abstract
free-floating rhetoric.
Can
there be any type of justification for killing
millions of animals?
I don’t
think there’s any justification for it. One
can give reasons as to why one does it. But it
can’t be justified. One has to be careful not
to not to confuse explanations with
justification. It’s important to keep the
gaping wound open. Crimes against animals
cannot be glossed over.
Does
the injustice lie in the fact that animals are
deprived of their right to be eaten and
instead get burned to death?
This is a
sophistic argument. No, the injustice toward
animals begins much sooner. When animals, in
Hegelian terms, are a priori produced merely
as beings in the service of beings other that
themselves and when their purpose of existence
is determined by a restless, reckless, empty
consumption. There is something fundamentally
wrong with this. It raises fundamental
questions about intensive livestock farming.
Intensive livestock farming does not belong to
the farming tradition; rather it is an evil
synthesis of nomadic animal breeding customs
and modern meat-capitalism.
Do you
believe that there will be the possibility of
practicing the genetic altering of animals
thoughtlessly in the future? Will it be
possible to speak of animals á la carte? This
would contradict your vision of animal
emancipation.
We’re
moving toward a medically-dominated society. A
medical-pharmaceutical-biotechnical complex is
taking shape which wrestles with the greatest
illusions of vitality. Health myths, illusions
about immunity and life-extension are coming
to take the place of religion. Already today,
life-extension is a widespread option. Modern
people do not want keep too much guess work in
life. Otherwise it will drive them to a
metaphysical superstructure. Life-extension
that has been developed by present day
medicine removes a great deal of the
metaphysical pressures from our lives in that
it eliminates the need for the many subsequent
demands of an unfulfilled life as in the
Middle Ages. The modern individual wants to
die like Job once did: old and satisfied with
life. This is the basis for the
medically-dominated complex.
Will
there be human beings á la carte, conforming
to the most bizarre wishes?
No, the
ideal of human formation will not be
purposefully damaged. Just as before, we will
experience monster shapes and hybrid forms as
something horrible and shutting out horror
remains an effective means. Once again we will
understand the concept of monster from its
origin. The word, as etymologists explain,
comes not from the Late Latin, monstrare,
to show; rather from the Classical Latin
monere, to admonish. They surface among
people as signs from the hereafter. Monsters
were the envoys of the gods. They carried a
mandate of evil. Through them, we once held,
the gods wanted to impart admonitions and
signs. This perception of the monstrous will
probably come back again soon under a
different omen. Because by nature there will
be some anomaly stemming from the general
human biotechnological level-headedness and
even when some attempts will possibly succeed,
it is foreseeable that many of them lead to
the formation of monsters. Because we stand
before man-made catastrophes of human
formation and we will speak about these
admonitions. This pushes us to a new level of
monologues. Monsters are mirrors of ourselves.
Can it
not be seen in the inverse: If genetic
modification will make people more and more
perfect, then aren’t we the monsters, we who
remain from the time before the biotechnical
age and were created in the archaic fashion?
I take
horror novels and horror theories for that
what they are, as entertainment. Targeted
biotechnical human creation will not,
according to the knowledge we now have, be
realistically attainable for a long time. What
is currently being discussed by the human
improvement party seems very, very speculative
to me.
Have
we made ourselves?
Yes,
human beings are genetically cultural beings
that have changed their biological structure
through extended stays in the house of
cultural inclinations. Neoteny plays a
decisive role in the special biological
development of humans. The retention of youth
forms and even of fetal formations up into
adulthood speaks for this. I have met
molecular biologists and sociologists who
never even heard of the term. For example the
fact that human faces have no snouts is a
cultural effect.
Does
the euphoria over the deciphering of the human
genome relativize the fact that certain human
dimensions are still unknown?
We still
are not able to decipher nearly as much as is
often claimed. According to what we hear,
biologists are still only able to understand
only one or three percent of the genome. The
German Nobel prize winner Nüsselein-Vollhart
is of the opinion that we don’t even really
understand a single gene that is we are not
able to grasp it in its full functioning. To
understand the genome is the work of a
century. I think that geneticists will soon
need the help of cultural philosophers in
order to ask more intelligent questions on
genes. The way in which the material is
currently questioned is medically-coded and
exclusively medically-oriented. This is too
narrow of a perspective. We are looking for
dispositions for disease. This is a one way
street for research.
Recently you had a conversation with the
genetic researcher Craig Venter, which left us
feeling a bit puzzled. Are not the questions
that we are currently discussing more
interesting than Venter’s motivation for his
research?
This is
what Venter and the American ambassador who
was also there in Lyon also thought. But in
that case it was a misunderstanding. For me
the point was not Venter’s motivation. I
wanted to place him within the Cultural
Revolution that stems from the American
Revolution, as Harold Bloom has referred to
the phenomenon. We are experiencing the
formation of a hyper-ideology for the
networked world: the fusion of stock market
illusions and bio-illusions. The two greatest
systems of illusions are growing together that
have appeared in human history up until now:
the religiously vital and the economic
dynamic. The first has to do with spiritual
life success, with choosing and blessing with
a sort of metaphysical immunity. The second is
about an economic success, the I-forming
satisfaction over growing accounts and status
gains. This situation presents us with a new
intellectual task: to grasp what happens when
these two illusionary- and immunizing systems
merge with one another.
Do you
mean a bio-Calvinism of sorts?
Perhaps
that is the right expression. Because it’s
high time to describe this American religion
or the resulting bio-religion more precisely.
For this reason I have used the opportunity to
make a few suggestions to Craig Venter, as to
how he can position himself as a proponent of
this movement. He did not accept these
suggestions in the Lyon situation. Instead he
has served us with a skeptical version of his
own interpretation, which in no way means that
a more enthusiastic version does not exist. I
know two speeches by him in which this comes
through very clearly. One from June 26, 2000
as he stood next to Clinton, allowing his to
gaze wander beyond the end of the millennium
and then revealed his great vision; and
another one which he held before Vietnam
veterans and traces his work back to this time
stating that he had survived the war and
wanted to do something big and important with
his rescued lie. This shows that Venter has
the ability of tapping into more than one
inventory of vocabularies and experiences. He
can take on mournful or agnostic tones at
will. In my opinion this is proof of
extraordinary intelligence.
Venter
has practiced an appropriate rejection of
metaphysics with regard to you, up until the
statement that he allegedly researched the
genome because he wanted to buy himself a
bigger sailboat. Did you demand too much from
him?
Probably.
But even if the temptation for cooperative
philosophizing did not work, at least he has
reacted in a way that demonstrated that he was
thoroughly and exceptionally intellectually
present. I was only not able to move him to
theoretical acrobatics.
Does
this lie in the fact that a deep-seeking,
worry-ridden European asked a happy
researching American? Was there an
intersection of two cultures?
That’s
how it can be seen. One should however not
underestimate the European advantage in this
confrontation. In the last one hundred years,
Europeans have learned how to withdraw from
imperial overstretching. The Americans, in
contrast, still have the missionary, naïvely
expansive view that belongs to the assumption
of leadership through neophytes. When it is
stated that the Europeans have forfeited their
position of leadership, one mus also add to
that that it was perhaps the best thing that
could happen to them. Economically, they were
able to keep a leading position and cede the
disadvantages of political dominance. There is
now a volunteer that disencumbers Europe.
Actually, Europeans feel a lot more
comfortable in their mild skepticism toward
progress than they are willing to admit. The
widespread enthusiasm for America does not run
deep in Germany and in Europe. They applaud
Americans but do not want to be like them.
They lean back a bit and unsurprisingly it is
an armchair on which they are leaning and it
is an expensive, well-made director’s
armchair. They lean back only lightly in order
to feel more relaxed and to make more leve-headed
decisions. The European style of exercising
power has become more discreet. This could
mean that it possesses more control and
sustainability and can prove itself more
capable of enduring in the long run than any
naïve surge ahead and take charge kind of
attitude with projects in which one can
virtually not know where they will lead.
For
this reason retroactive appeals function so
poorly here.
Roman
Herzog experienced this and future appeals
politicians will experience this in the
future. The Europeans no longer participate in
volunteer mobilizations/ Is this not a great
advantage?
Is
this also valid for the gene technology
revolution? Sometime we perceive politics
shying away from this topic.
Europeans
await the monsters just as they once did for
the barbarians. We are looking out for
incidents in which the gene technology
euphoria will break. But we know that it can
continue even without the euphoria. Everything
that can be incorporated into solid success
stories will here also become part of the
culture. The Europeans and the Germans as
well, will not deny themselves the tiny steps
of progress in gene technology. Just that the
Europeans have practiced this hang-gliding
over the abyss too often in the last century.
The
new cultural minister Julian, Nida, Rümelin
claims that embryos have no human worth. What
do you think? As of when is a person worthy of
having human worth?
When one
asks these questions, one is already on the
wrong track. One must simply know that the
concept of human worth is thoroughly shaped by
old European substance metaphysics. If one is
going to use these terms then one should do it
consistently and grasp it in its entirety. The
tiniest part of a substance is still only a
substance. The question as to when a human
life should really begin to be honored as such
is nothing more than the Catholic way of
talking about human worth because they see the
early cells of humans as being just as sacred
as the grown imago. Unfortunately, those who
hold this position don’t express themselves
clearly in most cases because they are too
cowardly to avow themselves to a decisive
metaphysical position. Cowardice generates
confusion and the confusion produces
pseudo-debates. The discussion of human worth
is a metaphysical semantic game that only
makes sense under its own premises. As soon as
one transfers this debate into secular, legal
and philosophical language it falls into an
existential crisis out of which it comes
defeated.
How
should one then discuss when human life
begins?
I would
prefer to use the concept of guardianship.
Legally and psychologically, this concept is
sufficiently clear and expresses the idea that
there are relationships among people, that are
also binding and to a high degree especially
when one end of the relationship is not able
to exercise its self-assertion. This applies
directly to children. A successful human life
stems from a stage of guardianship. This is
reminiscent of the insurmountable necessity of
guardianship s the highest form of solidarity
even when one has to come to terms with the
fact that this concept will attract a bunch of
neurotic and autistic prejudices against the
power of the guardians. I am convinced that a
generous and thoroughly thought out theory of
guardianship will preserve us from many of the
absurd side effects of an overreaching
discourse on human worth.
Are
you only thinking of guardianship for children
that are already here?
Not only
as such. There is, as I stated earlier, a
guardianship for the unborn and the never
born. A type of immigration takes place in
every society. By this I don’t mean those from
the outside but those from the inside, the
biological immigrants of every new generation.
These immigrants don’t make their entry
through external borders, but through mothers.
And even here a politics of immigration has
always existed. Never have societies welcomed
all of their immigrants indiscriminately:
neither the ones that wanted to come in from
the outside, nor the ones that sought to come
in from the inside. In the case of biological
immigration the role of the border control has
always lain with the mothers; they play the
roles of the immigration officers. They are
the ones that decide who will be let in and
who will not; this has been a woman’s right
since time immemorial. One has to come to a
consensus over this fact in order to begin
discussing principles.
In the
case of “surplus” embryos the immigration
officers are not mothers but doctors.
Here one
can reasonably apply the rule of the graded
protection services. You interpret the margin
for the earliest forms of potential human life
as undefined and that is located on the lowest
step of protection. Of course the embryo that
is only a few days old has a right to
provision. But there are a series of
exceptions and evasions that go with that.
This lies in the nature of this question, as
one already knows with natural events. Every
third or fourth menstruation cycle is a
spontaneous rejection due to a refusal to
allow an organism to nest in one’s body. Yet
women in most cases have no idea about this.
As soon as the maternal organism has allowed
the nesting to take place, one will agree to a
higher level of protection worthiness.
What
does this speak for?
That the
concept of a graded protection worthiness we
come closer to real life circumstances and the
moral intuitions of human being than with an
abstract general concept of person that one
can only implement at the expense of the
implausibility of embryos in the four-cell
stage. Most of them factually operate with a
three-step plan, that has been preserved: from
the beginning the fertilized egg and the
invisible embryo are under the protection of
their natural and legal guardians, who could
both use greater leeway in making
determinations; in the next step the implanted
embryo enjoys a higher level of immunity
because of its manifest presence and its
intimate welcome through its mother. The
immunization goes even further when toward the
middle of the pregnancy a soul in the
traditional sense, enters the picture. At this
point a ring of protection fully encloses the
new life; from that point onward we are
dealing with a human being whose rights may be
denied by no one, under any pretexts
whatsoever.
What
lies before human worth? Integrity?
Many
overextended ideas circulate over integrity.
One speaks of the integrity of a disabled
life, of the right to incompletion, of the
right to be conceived and not made. In such
formulations lie some pleasant ideas in part,
but they are tied to a problematic tendency to
capitulate to discoveries. With all due
respect to theology: nature is a already a
single improvement process and at the same
time an innumerable gene copy error. I reject
the theological transfiguration of hereditary
diseases. I don’t believe in the God that
created hare-lips. Of course, I can understand
that many find it scandalous that very soon
therapeutic improvements will be attempted on
embryos or even on the blastocyst. But to have
malformed children come out of evolution is at
least just as scandalous.
But
won’t it get to the point where everything
that does not correspond to an ever increasing
demand of perfection become a disability?
There is
a danger in this. But it does not stem from
gene technology per se but from an infantile
model of thinking of narcissistic people. The
perfectionism of dimwits is dreadful. How can
this be prohibited? As a matter of fact ideas
of breeding of a superman, a sturdy human or a
talented mutant are surfacing above all in the
United States at present. But this is
laughable both from a moral standpoint and
from an anthropological one as much as the
idea of a retro-breeding of humans to the
fighting apes of the Darwin era was
ridiculous. On the other hand, one must be
careful not to allow genetic crackpots to
practice applied science fiction in isolated
laboratories. But in this condensed world such
developments are to be feared less than many
believe. Even anomalies will sooner or later
be resocialized by the technological
community. Only serious gene technicians have
an authentic cultural mandate.
In
most cases there is no chance of curing
disabled embryos because diagnostic medicine
is far more advanced than therapeutic
medicine. Consequently the therapy consists in
killing the embryo. Doesn’t the right to be
cured transform itself into the right of not
having to have to exist?
Many
styles of parenting will be developed from
this. Many people will want to keep
procreation under the veil of ignorance;
others will intensively occupy themselves with
the possibility of genetic precautions. The
theory and practice of biological guardianship
gains more territory. This is a trend in our
culture since the introduction of
contraceptives. The provision will extend to
an area that has not been reachable because
the technical premises were not present. It
will be ever more difficult to engage in naïve
parenting.
The
way in which a human being should become
should be decided in conversations between
medical hegemonists, as you refer to them, and
the worried or overly worried parents. These
then lead to a rational debate over the
biological prerequisites for a successful
life. Isn’t this terrible since something
which cannot be decided through reason is
being decided rationally?
Yes, this
is an accurate insight. Decisions don’t not
usually forced by reasons. Decisions always
require the risk of a leap. Reason for anxiety
sets in if one were able to create future
generations optionally and produce complex
characteristics intentionally. This remains a
fable for the foreseeable time. The prevention
of hereditary diseases of the severest type
is, as soon as this becomes possible, not an
unholy machination but an expression of
responsibility. There are borderline
situations in which the parents must decide
for a demand for life as informed guardians.
There is no way of getting around this.
Can
one or should one set fixed policy as to which
disabilities should be aborted?
Politics
can, may, and must do whatever is in its
reach, but it can never do this alone again.
It will have to be surrounded by a circle of
consultants. All decisions must be an outcome
of discussions and must be embedded in checks
and balances. Our society has gotten so
complex and so rich in inhibitory and
compensatory mechanisms that really big
idiocies succeed in having a long life.
Our
situation is more determined by the fact that
no one is ready any longer to formulate norms
that are not already relativized in the act of
expressing them. There is the danger related
to this that we will sink into discursive goo.
Absolute idiocies can be committed in this
type of scenario over which one can be
artfully deceived. Doesn’t one need a group
like the Catholic Church, which is naïve, yet
clever enough to set clear boundaries?
As far as
naiveté goes, I see no danger that could
escape us. There is always enough ignorance
and there will be no want for advancing
decisiveness. What is important is to have a
mechanism in place that will balance the
naiveties and the fundamentalisms.
The
position of naiveté is much trickier today
because it is, at least in the case of the
Church, in a way, an enlightened naiveté. It
is aware of the contours it gives the debate.
The Church however secretly doubts itself as
it pronounces its position.
For this
reason I am looking for a more encompassing
term for naiveté. It has to capture the
readiness on the part of people to make
decisions. The ability to make decisions
presupposes leaving certain aspects
unconsidered and not thinking certain thoughts
through. This naiveté is indestructible.
The
state surrounds itself with consultants. The
Federal Chancellor wants to have a national
Council on Ethics. Would you participate in
it?
My answer
depends on whether it is you who is asking me
this or the Federal Chancellor.
*
This interview was translated from the
original German and re-published with the
permission of Dr. Heik Afheldt.