hen
American abstract painting was hailed triumphantly in
the sixties, the mantle of the avant garde passed from
the School of Paris to the School of New York. Or did
it? The second-most important element of the School of
Paris, the virulently hostile French bourgeoisie that
formed its easily-provoked early audience (there were
riots at the first Paris performance of Le Sacre du
Printemps), was long gone; and even if it had
still existed, the avant garde, like the gothic style
of the late Middle Ages, was a local wine that
traveled poorly. They did, after all, call it the
School of Paris. Since the avant garde left
such a rich inheritance, acknowledging this doesn’t
detract from the importance of subsequent modern
art—it merely acknowledges that claims to rival the
School of Paris
were doomed. Early American vanguardists, for
instance, from Dove to Hartley, encountered withering
isolation of a sort unimaginable to European artists
for trying to introduce avant garde content to a
society that was so different from that of Europe.
One of these
differences was the American social dynamic created by
successive waves of massive immigration. Early in the
twentieth century, several writers grew concerned
about the too rapid vault toward assimilation by
immigrant groups. The social critic Randolph Bourne in
particular worried about individual ethnic mores that,
he wrote, somehow failed to influence America’s
traditions and expressions. Over these bearers of
ancient vital cultures fell, he thought, the pall of a
conformist, shallow Anglicization.
The Anglo Saxon element is guilty of . . . the
imposition of its own culture upon the minority
peoples. The fact that this imposition has been so
mild, and indeed, semi-conscious, does not alter its
quality.
Bourne urged
an
examination of what Americanization might rightly
mean. . . . It is apparently our lot to be a
federation of cultures. . . . we find that we have all
unawares been building up the first international
nation . . . America is already the world federation
in miniature.
Bourne’s vision of open cultural federation, however,
was not to be realized. The nineteenth through the
mid-twentieth century was an age of Anglo-melt, and
the price of joining was ethnic concealment. Newcomers
anglicized the names of their children, aped
Protestant attitudes and manners, and spoke English in
public. To display ethnic character invited derision;
the melting pot was based on emphasizing apparent
similarities and suppressing obvious differences. The
process of assimilation and the world it created are
at the core of the American aesthetic in literary no
less than visual art, and has often been written
about. One especially poignant book, Call It Sleep,
Henry Roth’s 1930s masterpiece, uniquely describes
growing up in a New York City ghetto near the turn of
the century.
Roth’s novel explores
some of the forces that powered assimilation and the
price young immigrants had to pay to survive
(surprisingly, Roth’s model for immigrant assimilation
would also come to serve Abstract Expressionism).
Roth’s main character, the young, sensitive, Lower
East Side-dweller David Schearl, is supported by a
protective mother who transmits to him a world of
culture. In a book with great feeling for language,
English, the tongue of the New World, is rendered in a
butchered speech without nuance, while the translated
Yiddish David speaks at home is rendered as elegant,
delicate and complex. Isaiah Berlin, speaking of the
eighteenth century German philosopher, poet and
historian Johann Gottfried Herder, exactly captured
this culture formation in his description of people’s
urgent need to retain their sense of place:
Herder virtually
invented the idea of belonging . . . just as people
needed to eat and drink, to have security and freedom
of movement, so too they need to belong to a group. .
. . To be human meant to be able to feel at home
somewhere, with your own kind. Each group, according
to Herder, has its own . . . set of customs and a life
style, a way of perceiving and behaving that is of
value solely because it is their own. The whole of
cultural life is shaped from within the particular
stream of tradition that comes of collective
historical experience shared only by members of the
group.
Roth, seen through
Herder’s lens, is carefully delineating how the only
route to full culture can be blocked by American mores
that require a path which suppresses open
acknowledgement of one’s own culture.
For David,
the contrast between the delicacy and considerateness
of his home life and the brutality and indifference of
the world around them is overwhelming, and eventually
the delicacy and structure of his internalized
immigrant world is destroyed. He becomes overwhelmed
by the frustration of his childish efforts to
understand his situation. When his world finally tears
apart, he too is torn, and David experiences, in an
uncharacteristic outpouring—almost like speaking in
tongues—a raw energy that pours through him in a wild
flow: “He fled through to the street, one wild glance
at his house and he scurried west. A strange chaotic
sensation was taking hold of him. . . . I’m somebody
else . . .” David experiences a remarkable surge in
physical energy in the context of his self-negation,
and the invulnerability it bestows on him is striking:
“Ain’ even tiad! Ain’ even me!”
But
the point is clear: a child has made a sacrifice that
has wiped out much of his identity, in the process
releasing an energy that makes the melting pot work.
American subjugation of self to public identity was
aggressively spelled out by the young Richard
Rodriguez, a writer with what one might call a
combination of overseer’s complex and Stockholm
Syndrome. Like Roth, Rodriguez focuses on themes of
American acculturation in an autobiographical
narrative called Hunger of Memory, published in
the 1970s. Young Rodriguez, like Roth, speaks of the
social self-obliteration and self-surrender of a
sensitive and shy Hispanic child in the parochial
school system, but unlike Roth, Rodriguez embraces and
celebrates it.
Only when I was
able to think of myself as an American, no
longer an alien in gringo society, could I seek
the rights and opportunities necessary for full
public individuality. . . . despite the fact
that the individuality I achieve in public is
often tenuous—because it depends on my being one
in a crowd. |
For Rodriguez, who
attacks the “brazen intimacy” of teenagers speaking
black English to each other, the outcome of the war
between public and private is an emptying of a
once-privileged realm. Bilinguists, he declares,
do not seem to realize that
there are two ways a person is individualized . . .
while one suffers a diminished sense of private
individuality by becoming assimilated to public
society, such assimilation makes possible the
achievement of public identity. . . . only in private
. . . is separateness from the crowd a prerequisite
for individuality. . . full individuality is achieved,
paradoxically, by those who are able to consider
themselves members of the crowd.
Public space, the
neutral area in which Americans interact away from the
precincts of intimacy and their private lives,
continues to be a social and political necessity,
despite the truth of Bourne’s insights, because—in
this Rodriguez was right—our heterogeneity necessarily
defines the place where we meet almost as if we were
all strangers. Up until the sixties and seventies, the
sobersides business culture, tonally void of character
save for echoes of its long-gone WASP founders, served
as an inert behavioral model for the more expressive
subcultures. Rodriguez’s idealization of public space
as a value in itself and an eradicator of the cultures
for which it stood in as placeholder exemplified
assumptions that came to be destructive both to the
cultures under attack and to public space itself. This
idealization ended the taken-for-granted neutrality of
public space. Later on, it also stimulated a
resistance that lead to activist agendas and
ultimately to the landmined PC mentality of identity
politics. Bourne’s vision of America as a nation of
many strong cultures could ultimately be a recipe for
political disaster (as it has been in the Balkans),
but it is achievable microculturally. Rodriguez’s
solution, to take away from people what can’t be taken
away—their identity—and replace it with whatever gives
us presence in public space, was an attempt to
substitute crab apples for oranges.
Nothing could have
been further from the European avant garde experience
than that of Roth and Rodriguez. The School of Paris
successfully attacked the larger world with eccentric
individual vision and style, not the other way around.
Ambitious European outsiders like the Fauvist painters
didn’t need mass support—they could arm themselves
with theories and produce manifestos to justify their
surprising art. They established themselves through
the strength and definiteness of their ideas, which
needed to resonate only in a few appropriate places in
their class-structured world to achieve a degree of
security and recognition.
In America, by
contrast, the Fauvists would have had trouble
registering. As a fascinated and somewhat alarmed de
Tocqueville put it in the early nineteenth century,
“No longer do ideas, but interests only, form the
links between men, and it would seem that human
opinions were no more than a sort of mental dust open
to the wind on every side and unable to come together
and take shape.” In the New World, dissenting thought,
even robust social experiments, would arise but tended
to disappear, leaving scarcely a trace. Commenting
further on the way ideas lost their status in the
American climate and were replaced by the power of
consensus, de Tocqueville wrote that “the idea of
rights inherent in certain individuals is rapidly
disappearing from the minds of men; the idea of the
omnipotence of the authority at large rises to fill
its place.” In a rather chilling assessment of these
developments, the historian John Patrick Diggins,
author of The Lost Soul of American Politics,
has written that “society [was forming] as a
self-regulating entity whose laws operated not only
independently of the political state but [was] held
together by unconscious needs and desires, society as
something alien to the self.” Rodriguez’s violent
self-cleansing was performed in the name of this
society.
Early vanguardists
were required to enter our society of strangers and
create an aesthetic to fit, not challenge, the vast,
neutrally-defined arena of public space. Abstract
Expressionism sought to move the capital of world art
from Paris to New York. But to be a Frenchman in
Paris, the hub of centralized French politics and
culture, is to be at the center of a cultural
orchestration that never misses a beat. From Alsace to
Normandy, identity in this Herderean universe is
simply a fact; each Frenchman’s political and cultural
birthright, locally and nationally, are seamlessly
one.
To watch a busy Paris
street is to watch a rhythm. The processes of
acculturation are profound—so profound that a French
painter’s own taste could become the national style,
as Jean Renoir reports his father’s did. By
comparison, New York City has rhythm, but not a rhyme:
it is always thrilling to come back to the city after
an absence and with a fresh eye encounter the
unanticipatable melee of styles that a New York street
affords—a near chaos in which each citizen is working
out his own pursuit of happiness in his own way and at
his own pace, just trying not to bump into anyone
else. The Founding Fathers, who bestowed on us the
right to the pursuit of happiness, left the individual
relatively disconnected and without context. The early
removal of the capital of the country to
out-of-the-way Washington, D.C., to preserve the
federal government from local political influences,
cut the individual off from a sense of participation
in central decision-making, leaving an apolitical,
unmoored citizenry and making federal power seem
remote and irrelevant to local interests. Abstract art
played a significant role in the expansion of
idealized public space. The European tradition of an
art that established niches and boundaries needed to
be transformed into an art of identification in which
boundaries dissolve. The two traditions are profoundly
different: the former often involves respect for what
you can’t identify with. When in the nineteenth
century Oscar Wilde addressed American coal miners
wearing velvet knee britches and they cheered him,
Wilde’s audience was accepting, not identifying with
him. When the identity of a community is secure
enough, as in Herder’s universe, it is possible for it
to accept an alien element, as the coal miners
accepted Wilde for his guts, his performance, and his
britches. When gay theater, the most original theater
in the 1960s heyday of Off-Off-Broadway, finally
emerged from midnight, out-of-the-way performances, it
engaged in a debate about self-presentation. The
decision was made by key players like Charles Ludlam
and the general gay community that their theater
should not publicly formulate its aesthetic and
worldview as one openly different from heterosexual
theater’s, but present itself more as an already
included, attractive ethnic group, as in, “There’s a
little Italian in each of us.” The proffer of
identification, unlike that of acceptance, means that
the audience is being offered more social and personal
space to expand into. This form of art, which expands
public space, helps explain why in America cultural
innovations that start out with considerable character
rapidly turn into mere trends once the move toward
“the center” is made. The center, rather than being a
location equidistant from two extremes, as is
invariably represented, is actually a loose puddle
that erodes structures which express character.
Abstract
Expressionism was well on its way to a rendezvous with
public space long before the gay theater. Its avatars
too had their own strategies. In a world where society
itself pre-empted alienation, the alienation of the
artist, foundation of the European avant garde,
couldn’t register. So would-be American vanguardists
did not attack their equivalent of the bourgeoisie—the
middle class—but worked to convince Americans that
modern art was not as far from middle class interests
as provincial reactions of rejection might lead one to
think. The author of How New York Stole the Idea of
Painting, Serge Guilbaut, noted that in 1943, in
an effort to help gain acceptance for their painterly
convictions, two painters—Mark Rothko and Adoph
Gottleib—wrote to The New York Times to explain
that their movement (Abstract Surrealism, which was to
become Abstract Expressionism) sought “simple
expressions of complex thoughts.” Their ambition—to
field a “just us folks” version of abstract art—is
telling. First, as an aesthetic posture, it’s more
than a little condescending—a hypocritical tone
invites the audience to participate in its own dumbing
down. Second, their formula may set a limit on
accomplishment—in a discipline like art, whose high
achievers have always been famously single-minded, a
calculating preoccupation with packaging complexity to
look simple risks having marketing considerations
interfere with artistic interests. Practically,
however, Gottleib and Rothko weren’t misguided; they
were merely seeking to broach an American resistance
toward abstract work whose intensity sometimes masked
a certain empathy. As an example of backhanded
appreciation, consider the words of a disapproving
Chicago critic who wrote of Duchamps’s Nude
Descending a Staircase: that “it looks like an
Omaha lumberyard in the tornado season”—a brilliantly
empathetic image that suggests the painting had struck
home. But even when abstract painting struck a
responsive chord, the road to acceptance was rugged.
Abstract
Expressionism overcame these obstacles by changing the
tentative explorations of Abstract Surrealism into an
intellectually unthreatening form that Americans could
identify with—painting that emphasizes itself as an
act (in fact dubbed Action Painting by the critic
Harold Rosenberg). A material gesture in paint is an
incontestable material fact that could serve as the
simple expression Rothko and Gottleib sought.
Difficult to unpack and as incontestable as a small
avalanche, gesture could compellingly stand as a force
whose literal actuality could override and mask
whatever it carried along. Action Painting’s
immediacies, in other words, grow from an impressively
physical style that foreclosed interpretation while
encapsulating the emotive resonance of the
broken-surface brushstroke of, for instance,
Rembrandt, Velazquez and Rubens. These seventeenth
century painters confirmed and celebrated the European
tradition that the freely released painterly gesture
can bear with it not just material, but feeling. The
European painterly gesture created elements of an
image into which feeling had been infused by virtue of
the hand of the artist, expressing, sometimes
miraculously, both his body and his mind. In this way,
the School of New York, offering the same tradition in
a wholesale form, in an instant stroke delivered to
the emptiness of public space the fullness of culture.
The contradictions
inherent in this posture were as massive as the
paintings themselves, since it was a question whether
painterly values could be detached from European
contexts hardly reflected in American experience. For
the most part, the American aesthetic for which
physicality is deliberately central, for instance, is
a hand-me-down from the era of the Genteel Society in
the latter part of the nineteenth century, when, as
Santayana observed, men took on the bully
work—continent taming, exploring and building a great
nation and great business empires—“The House of Will,”
as he put it—while women, in control of manners and
morals, controlled the arts and writing—“The House of
Culture.”
In the nineteenth
century the thought and writing of the American
Renaissance bloomed with Emerson and his
contemporaries, and the rise of magazines, as the more
softly surfaced Genteel Tradition began to rule in
place of earlier, male-oriented Calvinism. Though the
majority of the new voices were still male, men in the
new context experienced frustration over the
difficulties of putting forward any aesthetic that
expressed male roles and a male authority that shared
characteristics with the purposive Calvinist model.
Complaining about the imperviousness of American
cultural thought to critique, Henry James, a
beneficiary of the new climate and himself
preeminently genteel, writing in frustration in The
Speech and Manner of American Women, complained
that this unapproachable style of cultural authority
defies the criticism
and the criticism, gasping at the impunity, is reduced
to the impotence of the traveler, waiting, carpet bag
of notes in hand, at a by-station, for the train that
whizzes past without stopping. Whence the wondrous
vicious circle—the train ignorant of a goal, but never
so much as slowing up, the traveler conscious of a
mission, but never so much as making a dash. Whence,
in other words, the rare perfection of the impunity,
assured in advance of the non-intervention of
criticism.
American male writers of the day—Twain, Thoreau, and
Melville, who were also beneficiaries of the new
society—were frustrated and reactively wrote books in
which women have no place (Huck Finn has no mother;
Moby Dick is virtually womanless). Moby Dick,
a masterpiece, was an early project of wounded
masculinism, which itself became an aesthetic as the
struggle to make art out of the man’s cultural portion
of triumphal, often physical work went on in the
writing of Hemingway and a multitude of others.
Abstract Expressionism, an art movement that barely
included women and fielded a massive, violent art with
concealed content, eminently belongs to this
tradition.
With their unfancy housepainter’s brushes and Duco,
the Abstract Expressionists associated themselves with
everyday blue collar journeymen and their
unexceptional materials, appropriating a democratic
status that seemed to bypass complex ideas and was
very different from the status European movements
derived from structured thought. Abstract
Expressionists, who were often indifferent to the
impermanence of their materials, abjured the
craftsmanship whose skills had conferred traditional
status on objects in Europe. In America, the values of
the craft tradition, suitable for limited production
of articles of quality, were obliterated by the need
for objects in quantity and the pressures of
technological change—the American designer of clipper
ships, when asked why his vastly superior vessels
weren’t put together with greater care and so didn’t
last, answered that it was because builders knew that
within a few years even better-designed ships would be
replacing them. The continent’s apparently endless
resources promised a vast flow of unspecified
materiality that could be directed to manufacture
whatever object was desired. This river of fluid
materiality was the New World’s democratic response to
the crafted, niche-creating status object, and it was
to this vast potentiality that Abstract Expressionism
turned, rather than to the precision and specialized
knowledge of the craftsman.
One all-important
aspect of the new role of the artist as unintellectual
aesthetic athlete was Abstract Expressionism’s near
total abdication to critics. In absolute contradiction
to the tradition of the European avant garde, whose
members were in control of their own theoretical
destiny and were witty, sharp-tongued and feared,
Abstract Expressionists handed over their voices to
critics, especially to Clement Greenberg. An arts
impresario almost without peer, Greenberg wrote for
The Partisan Review and worked in the 1930s, ’40s
and ’50s to make America the center of advanced
abstract art, engineering, as Guilbaut has described,
the shift from the School of Paris to the School of
New York. But the demand on artists to represent
themselves—a group of mature men who had mastered one
of the most difficult disciplines of the century—as
exuberantly witless, if occasionally oracular,
cowboys, was only one of several sleights of hand
required.
Given the differences
between Paris and New York, Greenberg had his work cut
out for him in creating a marketplace for American
abstract painting (which had been frozen out by
European work), leveraging the leap from third-rate to
world leader status in painting and displacing the
French-oriented galleries that then reigned in New
York City. First, he winnowed the number of artists to
be called Abstract Expressionists, much as Dutch
explorers when they discovered a Pacific island of
nutmeg trees immediately cut down three-quarters of
them, ensuring the scarcity that a strong market
requires. (For
instance, an artist named Janet Sobel made drip
paintings before Pollock, which the artist saw and
admired—and though Greenberg admitted they were the
first “allover” paintings, he pruned her from the
canon.) He
also insisted, in the very political aftermath of the
Depression, that the artists divest their work of
political intentions. Then he put abstraction on a
weight-loss program that roughly paralleled the one
endured by American women since WWII. On this artistic
journey, art would shed its “expendable
conventions”—all components of a painting that did not
point to its material elements as paint and canvas—in
order to arrive at a perfect, irreducible, inherent
flatness. Using technical language to apply this
highly selective reading of European aesthetic
developments that began with Cézanne (“I am the
primitive of a new art”), Greenberg claimed to be able
to identify the steps to the ideal of flatness that he
advanced as painting’s all and everything.
In doing so he
designed a historicist criticism that, like the stance
Henry James complained about, was able to bypass and
ignore the content of individual works—the sites on
which painterly value is actually created. In
contemporary formalist criticism, the critic Leo
Steinberg wrote, “The criterion for significant
progress remains a kind of design technology subject
to one compulsive direction: the treatment of ‘the
whole surface as a single undifferentiated field of
interest’. . . . there is rarely a hint of expressive
purpose, nor recognition that pictures function in
human experience.”
Easter Monday
The School
of New York can be said to divide into three parts,
the more buttoned-up, “uptown” artists (Gottleib,
Motherwell, Rothko, and Newman), the “downtown,”
bohemian-seeming expressiveness of de Kooning, Kline,
Gorky, and Pollock, and the explosive, color-saturated
work of Hans Hofmann, who wedded the German painting
tradition to American abstraction. Willem de Kooning
was the most central figure of the downtown group and
probably the painter who most justified the movement’s
second defining term, “Expressionism.” De Kooning’s
Easter Monday, painted in 1955-56, has
shallow space, powerful brushstrokes made with
housepainter’s brushes, traces of newsprint, and ranks
with masterworks of the School of Paris. It is deeply
anti-conventional in its indifference to elements that
hold a painting together, like internal reverberations
and echoings of color and shape; de Kooning’s painting
not only doesn’t cultivate such connective harmonies,
but seems to turn against them. The openness and
vulnerability of the painting seem to contribute to a
mood of ambivalence, even apathy. It is a powerful and
physical performance somehow laced with torpor.
Easter
Monday, as if it were made of debris and
litter, the continuous grinding of impacting edges and
pulverizing pressure, seems to suggest that in the
gutters of the urban mind all consciousness is
degradable. It is, incidentally, an extremely
difficult painting to hold in memory, in all
likelihood because the principles of its formation
seem to violate principles of coherence that help us
recognize landmarks and make the world seem familiar.
A
painting by de Kooning can brim with assertions which
never quite reach the level of full articulation; the
energy and tension of the work come out of a ferment
that generates an almost insurrectionary overtone of
part to whole. We would anticipate imminent riots were
it not for the densely shifting connections which
recoalesce just in time to avert bloody hell, but
which offer no more sense of permanent coalition than
flotsam. In fact, there seems to be an unusual
relation between the energy of the surface and the
passivity of its elements. Easter Monday
recalls Bourne’s earlier, rather black vision of
aspects of America, which he said, are “centrifugal,
anarchical. They make for detached fragments of
people. . . . they become the flotsam and jetsam of
American life, the downward tow of our civilization .
. . the cultural wreckage of our time . . . America
has as yet no impelling integrating force. It makes
too easily for the detritus of cultures. In our loose,
free country, no constraining national purpose, no
tenacious folk tradition and folkstyle hold the people
to a line.”
Easter
Monday
manifests an extraordinary American artistic vision,
an accomplishment of the first order even though it
offers us no way to cope with the condition it creates
beyond a relentless jockeying and parrying. Much of
its greatness, and for that matter the power of
Abstract Expressionism’s high aesthetic, comes from
faith in American ideals—like its use of the material
as a metaphor and a medium for universal, egalitarian
sharing. De Kooning’s work shows us how painting that
embraces and embodies the character of a remarkable
society can achieve great art, however peculiar that
society’s limits and the strictures placed on artists;
if Abstract Expressionism, like Moby Dick, has
at its heart a tragic misconception, it is not one
that barred the production of masterpieces.
Willem de Kooning, Easter Monday
1955-56; 96” x 74 |
Willem de Kooning, Woman I
1950-52; 76” x 58” |
Abstract
Expressionism’s aesthetic of
what-you-feel/see-is-what-you-get can’t help but
involve a kind of oblivion. For the benefit of
Everyone, the artist, as a somebody and as a class,
was to surrender his or her irritating separation,
which normally has been sustained by insider knowledge
about the means, history and tradition of the practice
of painting. The cost of Abstract Expressionism’s
appearing to relate so directly to the public, as if
Greenberg’s dictatorship of the aesthetic proletariat
had already succeeded, is that it circumvented the
reality of the special knowledge, traditions and even
the existence of the artistic communities from which
painting springs. This more direct relation to the
viewer was occasionally asserted in various ways by
different artists, who attempted to articulate the
authority of their art. Their comments stood, if
without much force, against the historical imperative
promoted by Greenberg’s criticism. Greenberg might be
guiding painting toward
ultimate
simplification graspable by all, but he was doing so
by manipulating the esoteric technicalities of
historical aesthetic
process. In
his
resistance to critical authority, Rothko could sound
wistful (“I’m not an abstractionist . . . I’m not
interested in the relationship of color or form or
anything else. I’m
interested
only in expressing basic human emotions—tragedy,
ecstasy, doom, and so on. And that a lot of people
break down and cry when confronted with my pictures
shows that I can communicate those basic human
emotions. . . .”); Newman fielded muscular and feisty
bluster (the artist declared that he preferred
questions about content, which he called “subject
matter,” to those about technical fact, which he
dubbed “object matter”); and de Kooning’s defense of
his deeply contradictory style was magisterial (he
had, he dismissively said, no interest in “abstracting
or taking things out or reducing painting to design,
form, line and color”).
The idea that a triumph over our external enemies in
World War II was to be followed by a triumphant
struggle within our own culture that transformed the
discomfort of our own alienation was a uniquely
American fantasy—a notion that Melville, for one,
would have appreciated. With the artist as a
touchstone and exorcist, the alienation of the artist
could substitute for the alienation of the society.
Unfortunately, the social alienation of public space
only superficially resembles that of the individual.
We
can see the results of this confounding in the
ambivalent Woman paintings of de Kooning, executed
with characteristics that appear at first glance to be
the essence of individual alienation: impassioned
brushwork, powerful color, exaggerated emotion,
obsession with the subject. De Kooning, however,
especially in this series of paintings, remained
locked in the bounds of public space, rather than
seeing his own alienation through, and he specifically
rejected catharsis. To challenge catharsis as the
engine of a too-comfortable humanistic art is
understandable; to reject connection is not. Catharsis
remains a part of the process by which individuality
comes to terms with its own alienation. There is no
entity, after all, to be made whole in the realm of
public space, and no one’s humanity to confirm; de
Kooning’s Women paintings (which should rank high
among the projects of wounded masculinity) have much
heat but little warmth. In this they are entirely
different from the works of one of de Kooning’s
masters, Soutine, who (by Greenberg’s account) used
paint with a powerful physical expressivity that makes
a positive, even Rembrandtian connection with the
subject. In de Kooning’s Women paintings, by contrast,
the emotionally violent painterly releases are
combined with a lack of connection or
identification with the subject. De Kooning’s deep
knowledge of painterly traditions notwithstanding, the
alarming image keeps looking not like a vision of
humanity that has achieved emotional reality, but like
the portrait of a panic attack that is not being dealt
with.
Les Demoiselles d’Avignon,
behind which Picasso is reported to have sat on a
chair for three days “in horrible moral isolation,”
embodies the fruit of individual alienation—daring
risk, idiosyncratic vision that reveals a challenging
and surprising version of reality, a need to visibly
connect with the past (if only in reaction) and to
reconcile vastly different forces (in this case the
psychological power of African masks, the classical
nude that echoes through the treatment of the figures,
the Mannerist skies of El Greco); it also shows a
desire to arrive at completion and closure. Public
space lacks a context for fathoming the urgency of the
artist’s need to make contact with traditions, or the
meaning of a statement like Kafka’s that the artist’s
work should be “the axe that destroys the frozen sea
within us.” The works of public space, in other words,
like the artist in a recent exhibition who shows
himself idly drinking a Coke before Buchenwald, can’t
entirely grasp the character of crisis or morality.
Warhol’s electric-chair and suicide paintings reassure
the consumer society that no matter what human horror
threatens, Pop’s aesthetic quotation marks can restore
the interests of the consumer to center stage.
Abstract Expressionism stabilized, if at an ultimate
price for some of its members, as an unrepeatable
moment in art, forming a fulcrum between two
worlds—Europe and America—and two epochs (the mid-20th
century and previous abstraction). But in practical
terms, what it had to offer would be confined to its
own generation. The Abstract Expressionists were
terrible parents.
The Sixties and After
What became of this
uniquely American movement over the next decades?
Something quite strange: in the early 1960s, without
explanation, American culture began its 90-degree turn
into Pop Art. For the many serious younger artists
whose artistic life was bound up with Abstract
Expressionism—and most serious young artists in New
York City then were—it was as if, without any public
announcement, a large cruise ship bound for the
Riviera suddenly began steaming toward Nome.
Astonishingly, the movement that put America on the
art map simply dropped away after one generation.
Although its artists continued to work and their
paintings appreciated in value enormously, they left
no path, and showing space for Abstract
Expressionist-influenced art began to dry up.
Abstract
Expressionism’s abrupt short-circuiting was due both
to the working out of Greenberg’s legacy, and the
Faustian bargain the movement made with his theory.
Greenberg’s reasoning masked several fault lines—to
begin with, the extreme heterogeneousness of the
movement’s members, who, because of differing artistic
intentions, would not have been called a movement
anywhere else in the world. Thanks to Greenberg’s
suppleness and determination, that issue never even
came up. His theories also conveniently skirted issues
of vanguard obligations on which they reneged (for
example, conforming to the standards of reigning
power, democratic or otherwise—though their swagger
and intransigence always made them seem rebellious).
Politically, his doctrine, claiming to shape
painting’s march to its ideal state, retained Marxist
elements that he deliberately concealed as the country
geared up for the Cold War. Guilbaut noted the strong
links between Greenberg’s theories and
the powerful Marxist
movement of the 1930s, to the crisis of Marxism, and
finally to the complete disintegration of Marxism in
the 1940s. . . . Greenbergian formalism was born from
those Stalinist-Trotskyite ideological battles, the
disillusionment of the American left, and the de-Marxification
of the N.Y. intellectual.
That many of the
artists developed in a leftist context was rarely
mentioned. Abstract Expressionism’s burden of
obscurity was heavy.
The surrender of
Abstract Expressionism’s artistic critical voice to
theoretical handlers was a disaster. Failure to
coherently express its artists’ views contributed to
the suppression of similar ideas in the next
generation. And while Abstract Expressionism’s
strategy of injecting a kind of orphaned high art
without name or reference into public space was
effective, the shock tended over time to wear off.
As the ’60s
approached, even Greenberg could not alter the fact
that his theory of “expendable conventions” had run
out of gas. An art was about to appear for which the
purity of the physical act would be irrelevant.
In December 1959,
Frank Stella presented a largish canvas with regularly
spaced dark diagonal black stripes at MOMA. The work
was applauded by Greenberg’s critical acolytes. With
artists now recast as “practitioners,” the “vanguard”
had turned into scribes whose mind experiments
formulated reductive theories and decided which
paintings fit them. Ultimately, these critics would
insist that their prescriptions were not just
guidelines for art practice but were in some sense art
itself.
Or such was their
fantasy. While it is impossible to say what art is or
predict what it will be, we can make one rule for what
art is not: when you get no more from a description of
a painting than you do from the painting, it falls
short (Stella’s painting fell short of art, a blank
canvas also isn’t art). Greenberg the art critic, who
spoke often of “quality” and would anoint a painting
with a cryptic “It’s good,” knew this perfectly well,
but Greenberg the art-theoretical
macher had
to accept his own logic, even though it had led
painting to the dead end of literalism. He theorized
that Colorfield painting was the successor to Abstract
Expressionism, but his absolutist reign was over, and
Greenberg was sidelined.
Aesthetics of the
American Center
A neutral arena for
public encounter is so necessary for our ethnically
varied mass society that it deserved to be better
protected, even from the ambitions of its champions.
But American victory in World War II and the Cold
War’s fierce competition so intensified the urge
toward an assimilationist make-over that this aspect
of our culture took on imperial overtones; in 1961 the
social critic Dwight MacDonald characterized the new
American center:
Masscult is a
dynamic, revolutionary force, breaking down the old
barriers of class, tradition, and taste, dissolving
all cultural distinctions. . . . . For the process
destroys all values, since value-judgments require
discrimination, an ugly word in liberal-democratic
America. Masscult is very, very democratic; it refuses
to discriminate against or between anything or
anybody.
Greenberg’s
theoretical arrogance, minus his love of quality, was
communicated to the Minimalists. Donald Judd simply
dismissed past art—his work, he said, entailed
“getting rid of the things that people used to think
were essential to art,” and “all the structure,
values, feeling of the whole European tradition. It
suits me fine if that’s all down the drain.” To
Minimalist theorists and many of their contemporaries
among the dizzying array of movelets—OP, Pop, Pattern,
etc.—the implicit connection of Abstract Expressionism
with European advanced painting had become irrelevant.
Robert Morris wrote that “the sensuous object,
resplendent with compressed internal relations,” the
result of a process of artistic empathy that empowered
an artist like Renoir when he sat before his subject,
whether a nude or a bouquet, “has got to be rejected.”
Some Minimalists, it should be said, like Tony Smith
and Anthony Caro, exhibited work with a broader, more
complex and engaging aesthetic. But with Judd and
Morris’s new, openly negative vanguard, which
aggressively defined itself more by what it wasn’t
than by what it was, the art scene engaged with what
could be called a Public Space Movement.
If every art movement
seeks its own audience by selectively cultivating some
aspect of the fluid, morphologically varied individual
persona, then
at the heart of the Minimalist universe dwells the
normative self.
Judd and Morris’s choice, the quotidian, unremarkable
normative self— Minimalism’s definition of order was
“just one thing after another,” practically a
definition of the normative—was an original one.
Ubiquitous and unsung except in focus-group circles
and by market researchers, our normative capacities,
necessarily on auto-pilot and not derailed by thought
or sunsets, had never been grist for an aesthetic;
they are designated merely to effectively get us
through daily tasks, from reaching for the OJ to
dealing with insurance documents. Tamped-down
subjectivity allows us when in person-as-statistic
mode to move fluidly through the crowd; such normative
preeminence, which art and especially the avant garde
classically challenge, wavers as soon as it loses its
focus. Morris’s Minimalist prescriptions train the
viewer to preserve the sense of routine.
Of course
subjectivity plays out in all human situations, but it
plays out differently; in public we are more
buttoned-down and guarded. But if, by virtue of a
condition everyone automatically
fulfills—physicality—the normative self could ignore
art’s challenges and become art’s constant and
unchallenged subject, Morris’s “non-personal or public
mode” would expand mightily. Behind such expansive
social friendliness, to which an aesthetic such as
Morris’s contributed, lay a rather aggressive spirit.
Claiming to overflow all boundaries, it became
programmatically impervious to culturally dissenting
voices within the indefiniteness that summed itself up
as the American middle class. The wave of narcissism
that swept over American arts and letters (Mailer’s
Advertisements for Myself was published in 1959)
for forty years persisted so long because it supported
the process with an insouciant accommodation posing as
dissent and dressed in sporty radical clothes.
The ideas that
accompanied the idealized melding of American society
may not have brought the art scene to the pinnacle of
art history, but came close to establishing one
landmark: world-historical mindlessness. On the high
end, critics, mostly in the universities, were
conducting an art dialogue of such rarefied
acceleration that artists might well have thought, as
some did, that to paint they needed first to master
Kant and then set forth on the slippery slopes of
deconstruction. On the other end, art that asserted a
degree of separation from social pressures encountered
a sea of feeble, uncritical opinion that swamped
serious thought. There was no way—echoing Henry James,
one might say no occasion—to contest, explain or
demur; many culturally oriented intellectuals,
convinced that the field of engagement had moved from
the canvas to the domain of their own thoughts, were
content to let the market be the test of ideas. The
function of galleries was to intrigue a curious, often
barely involved audience that was shopping for
spectacle but was also hoping that the rumor that
their personal lives were being enhanced was true.
Rivers of money were pouring into the art scene, and
for artists to be granted a stall at the art market
was to be granted validity, period—the vision of
salesmen needed no other standard. Art also fit well
into the age of therapy, as one more mode of expansion
for the citizen consumer. Internationally, American
art encouraged other cultures to believe that the most
insignificantly minor and trivial aspects of their
lives, soup cans for example, elevated to the iconic,
were every bit as important as the pleasures and
tribulations of the kings and saints whom art once
commemorated.
Despite the
continuing enthusiasm of the curators of major
American museums, in terms of any implicit claim to be
the cutting force of history, the aesthetics of Dwight
MacDonald’s Masscult have expired. As a New York
Times art critic wrote in April 2002,
What little good can
be said about the 2002 Whitney Biennial has been said.
It has been called noble, eclectic, generous and
inclusive—not inaccurate characterizations from
certain angles. But the latest version of this major
showcase of American art is also bleak, pious, naïve,
monotonous, isolated and isolating.
This assessment
suggests that if the Whitney curators were looking for
art that in any sense still honors avant garde ideals,
they didn’t know where, or perhaps how, to look. But
the exhaustion of officially sanctioned advanced
trends is only one marker of an era’s end. The
resistance to admitting the existence of repressive
and limiting boundaries within our society has been
idealistic and understandable, but by the late ’90s,
really, the unraveling of the aesthetic behind an
all-inclusive expansiveness was complete. The social
structures that supported it were no longer there:
·
The
American middle class has no longer been expanding,
but shrinking, as rapidly mounting disparities in
income reveal a class system. We are galloping toward
oligarchy. To protect itself the middle class will
openly define standards and make exclusions (of many
kinds—standardized tests, for instance), which cancel
the universality that the indefiniteness of middle
class boundaries was intended to sustain.
·
The
generation of the ’30s and ’40s, which championed the
virtues of idealized public space and brought to the
table—and to the Depression and World War II—a
desperate energy to succeed and a way to set the
American stage, has now passed. Its views and
strategies look as dated as an Odets play.
·
Pure
populist values, valid as they may be, have failed to
include everybody. Specifically, though it
enthusiastically made use of black and gay mores and
attitudes to recharge the blankness of the cultural
center, American middle class omniverousness has only
been able to partially digest the interests and the
identities of blacks and gays. Serious limitations
also continue to be placed on women’s interests.
·
The
blithe assumption that all people and cultures want to
be like Americans, and the effort to include them by
acting oblivious to their stated differences is
increasingly risky in a world of dangerous realities.
We have to understand people whose outlook is
different from our own.
·
New
immigrant cultures are not being broken down, or are
only partially going through the Rothian dynamic.
Their home cultures are only an airflight or e-mail
message away, and new cultural forms are necessary for
their assimilation.
Re: Bourne
It
. . . becomes easier to see that . . . some artists
have carried on trying to do what the first generation
of Abstract Expressionists attempted: they have tried
to find the forms through which they could bear
witness to lived experience with its present
pleasures, frustrations and potentialities. . . . when
the surveys of modern American art are written, the
art-historical tree is pruned in such a way that they
are eliminated. . . . the true history of art in
postwar America is yet to be written.
—Peter
Fuller
That Abstract
Expressionism was an implosion, curling away from the
future as well as the past, was revealed in the issue
of succession: Diana Crane’s The Transformation of
the Avant Garde, published in 1987,
chronologically charts Pop, Minimalism, Figurative,
Photorealism, and Pattern. (Colorfield should be
added, and why not throw in Trash painting like
Schnabel’s?) The succession of small movements that
followed Abstract Expressionism’s ascendancy, and the
critical ink on which they floated, seemed made to
illustrate Yeats’s canny observation that “reality is
not logical but can be made to seem so if logical
refutations are discovered of the writer or movement
going out of fashion.” Nowhere in Crane’s book is
there any indication of Abstract Expressionism’s most
obvious successor—a line of exploratory abstract
painting investigating abstraction in the expressive
tradition of the School of New York; as the polar
opposite of Minimalism, it could be termed Maximalism
(today it could be referred to as the “Slow Painting
Movement,” like Slow Food and Slow Cities).
Crane, however, was
responding only to lines of painting that fit the
culture of public space. These movements, where they
drew critical attention of any substance, were often
supported by the same academically oriented critics
who continued to address art issues as if they were
philosophical arguments, usually against a historicist
background that displaced or ignored the role of the
individual artist and ruled out expressive content.
In an unusual article
in The New Republic in October 1992, the art
critic Jed Perl spoke of the collapse of the American
art community, pointing out that in the past art and
artistic standards have been maintained by the
relationship between the “private art” world shared by
artists and the “public art” world which more directly
creates the art economy and reputations. (“In the
studios of New York—and, for all I know, across the
country—artists in their 30s and 40s and 50s and 60s
are making the incremental developments that are what
art is all about. . . . The support system of
galleries and grants and collectors and curators and
publications that makes it possible for artist to have
slow-developing, serious careers is in a state of near
total collapse. . . . There is simply no longer a
support structure that nourishes these incremental
developments.”) Pearl believes that “as the public art
world has become self-perpetuating, the private art
world has become increasingly isolated, fragmented,
frozen . . .”
To paint in a
non-homogenous culture with egalitarian ideals is a
messy proposition; aesthetic values aren’t
particularly concerned with fairness. Most aesthetic
values are by definition shared within particular
groups and are, however informally,
institution-creating, since values establish choice
and hierarchy, and this can always be interpreted as
unfairness—but what, for art, can be the alternative?
Despite its inegalitarian aspects, we inevitably see
with our values—and therein lies the value of seeing.
Artists who have made a success in the
content-undifferentiated contexts of public art as
Perl defined it have often fielded art that works
against openly displayed value, as does that of
David Salle, the leading “post-modern” painter of the
’80s. One Salle admirer, Janet Malcolm, saw his work
as “an art that refuses to be any one thing or to find
any one thing more interesting, beautiful, or
significant than another.”
Salle’s painting,
which can look peculiarly tepid to other viewers for
its very choicelessness and lack of passion, Malcolm
declared to be a “melancholy art of fragments,
quotations, absences” with “an appearance of
mysterious, almost preternatural originality,” even
though “nothing in it is new, everything has had a
previous life elsewhere—in master paintings,
advertising art, comics, photographs.” This is an
original use of the word original: Salle’s is
different from the startling originality of El Greco,
for instance, who, with genius, wedded two very
different traditions, the iconic and the Spanish.
The
effectiveness of Salle’s art, its ability to surf what
Salle termed “the din of the moment,” lies in the
contrast of its deceptively undefined qualities to
the more characterizable work of his contemporaries,
which then look passé to Malcolm. Of course the shelf
life of such art lasts only as long as it takes for
familiarity to set in. We can’t help but contrast El
Greco with other painters, admiringly, but not because
his work diminishes, eliminates or replaces theirs.
Broadening and intensifying Malcolm’s kind of quest,
Leo Steinberg in his essay “Contemporary Art and the
Plight of Its Audience” attempted to canonize painting
that treats human and aesthetic values negatively (his
example is Jasper Johns’s Target Painting,
which casually chops off the tops of a row of heads),
for the purpose of divorcing from them. He declares
that the resulting shock in the mind of a
knowledgeable viewer creates a valuable sense of
dread—but then so does bankruptcy.
Even when not being
so obliquely or directly hostile to values, other
critics, like Arthur Danto, focusing on the logical
outcomes of artistic trends and history as they see
it, have been unsympathetic to the process of slow
development Perl describes as sustaining art. By
itself critical analysis is a powerful tool, but can
become an arid, unfriendly environment for the
contexts of intimacy that contribute real value to
art. And when (despite Mailer’s wish-fulfillment
remark that “Democracy is culture”) an accomplished
and idealistic liberal society fails to admit that it
can’t satisfy its hunger for a rich psychic existence
through direct pursuit of its own conscious goals and
its sense of justice, an acute sense of starvation
amid plenty can result. (Such is the undernote sounded
throughout Trilling’s melancholy The Liberal
Imagination.) Far from isolating experience and
demanding an ever more purely physical aesthetic (Sontag’s
“Against Interpretation” comes to mind), an art that
can entertain suggestiveness, even seduction, is
closer to desire and its goals than the relentless
definition and stripping away of affect that our
society compulsively associates with freedom and
truth.
Yet as Fuller
protested, art with the contrasting values of
Maximalism has consistently been produced over the
last forty years—and it has sought, without special
drama, to grow into itself and move art forward. It
would be tempting to pick among Maximalists with a
list of examples from back when to now—say, Alan
Kleiman, Ray Spillenger, George Dennison, Angelo
Ippolito, John Evans, Liz Yamin, Peggy Jane Smith,
Lieby Miedema, Jan Sunderland, Nancy Storrow, Larry
Warshaw, Marty Greenbaum, Kim Tieger, Nora Kersh (and
one could go on)—but any one list can’t be typical of
Maximalism’s many scarcely known painters, who as a
whole seem to function something like a network of
participants in a SETI-like operation; geographically
separated though they may be and different as their
solutions may be, the consistency of the problems they
work on turns out to be surprising. We can’t catalog
with much accuracy the themes of artists we don’t, as
Peter Fuller pointed out, even know about, but we can
make a prediction—that Maximal art will turn out to
have been interested in personal as well as formal
discovery, seeking to extend and comprehend
abstraction through an art of exploration and play,
and that it built on precedents and innovation.
(For instance, the painterly impulses of Arshile
Gorky, informed by the traditions of the past and
reaching toward flight on a flat surface, introduced a
warm abstraction that grew out of an intimate frame of
mind and his unabashed identification with the
artistic traditions of his native Armenia.) As Peter
Schimmel wrote about the Abstract Surrealist model
that has frequently been the jumping-off place for
Maximalists, they worked with
a multifaceted,
multi-perspectival space in which images of the
unconscious, the sublime, the primordial and the
sexual could be suspended. . . . The
figure/ground relationship was constantly
explored and a tension created between the
linear elements that rest on the surface and the
vague illusion of a third dimension. . .
interweaving line and color, foreground and
background in a metaphorically rich primordial
brew.” |
Maximal art
doesn’t offer itself as the solution to the problems
of the century. It isn’t opera, chanting, sculpture,
sociology or an ethics class. It does value pleasure.
What especially fueled Maximalist art at its outset at
the end of the ’50s was the fact that beneath the
relatively taut skin of its well-run commercial
networks, post-war
America was
a cultural free-for-all with many competing groups and
zero orchestration. The United States had arrived at
the pinnacle of nations. For the first time, a
plurality of its citizens contemplated lifestyles that
had previously been the province of playboys. America
was waking up to the possibilities of life free of
WASP repression, and to be a Maximalist was to sense
that as a culture America was a global village in
pieces that needed to be sifted through and put
together, patiently and by
organic
process, by synthesis and cultural bridge-building, in
a Bournean spirit.
At the
beginning of the ’60s, a page had turned in the book
of Modernism: for artists entering early adulthood,
abstraction was in no imaginable way an act of
rebellion against long-vanished bourgeois reality,
and, no matter how much art critics demanded it in
order to make an impression on readers, little valid
ground remained for the drama, claims and swagger of
breakthrough art. No one knew what abstraction
divested of rebellion could mean or be—was it
necessarily neutral and technical, or could it be as
hot as a nude draped over a lusting bull? Was
abstraction suited to reach out to the global feast
that anthropology had revealed? What would be the
final destiny for the abstract ideas created by the
School of Paris?
The problems might be
daunting, the palette vast, and the precedents few,
but the prospects were great. Even taking into account
the appeal that self-isolation had for Abstract
Expressionism, so great was the promise of the era
that the movement’s infertility and (nearly uniquely
among significant art movements) its failure to bond
with young artists who sought to develop its
expressive content remains mysterious.
For the full art that
public space can’t produce, much less sustain, we need
forms that are complex, split, double, that connect
overarching American mores with our many cultural
communities, freeing public space from the damaging
burden of claiming to be everything for everyone.
Maximalist paintings poke around, establish surfaces
in the absence of pressure (a nearly insurrectionary
act in America), and even challenge Maximal painterly
intentions. While
it may invite analysis, Maximalist work seems to also
call for critical language shaped, like that of wine
aficionados, to communicate sensory experience.
Art that caters to
the normative, aside from risking sycophancy, too
greatly narrows imaginative realities that, by
definition, aren’t normative. Whether or not art
harbors elements of representation is a red
herring—Hofmann’s great abstractions, among others,
have taught us how our immediate grasp of the visual
world can become the basis for a mature abstract
art—abstraction doesn’t necessarily begin by rejecting
what we think we see. Maximal art over time is capable
of establishing viable new artistic conventions, in
pursuit of a spirit that was, sunnily and curiously
and at a moment of pressure when his career was
flagging, well expressed by David Salle: “To go
against the tidal wave of literalism and
literal-mindedness—to insist on and live the
life of the imagination . . . to be the experience,
instead of pointing to it . . . to have and give
access to feeling.” Salle’s naked, if boilerplate,
expression of optimism about what lies at the heart of
painting describes the very spirit that his style of
painting attempted to freeze—the embalmed quality of
his work triggered excitement in some post-modern
minds because of its imprisonment of content. For
these critics the attraction was hardly aesthetic:
Salle’s art offered the charm as well as the structure
of a hand grenade.
Mature work
establishes a less hidden relation to an artistic
optimism that may not be voluntary and not in the
power of the artist to withhold: an optimism that
blooms whenever the hand of the artist handles the
materials of art. The impasses of art in the face of
the radically open artistic possibilities of our time
means that our lease on the models through which we
expressed that optimism and the myths it gives rise to
has expired. But the prolonged delay in the
reformulation and discovery of new models isn’t
entirely the fault of the artists. Art doesn’t go on
in a vacuum;
the developing kind of work that Salle so
enthusiastically if belatedly endorsed has crucially
lacked support in American culture. In fact,
confirming Jed Perl’s fears, the forty-year
combination of market forces and Cold War ambitions,
along with a mighty boost from deconstruction and
Marxist criticism, may have desiccated the landscape
of art so thoroughly that repair is very difficult.
Over the last few
years theorists lost control; we have been left with a
welter of unrelated art styles that, added together,
approach William Empson’s definition of democratic
art: “One note each and the tune goes out free.”
Unfortunately, even good painting when stripped of
context may turn into mere cultural litter—each
painting, good or bad, becoming one more grunt added
to the infernal, moronic din. Paintings to be seen
need contexts the way fish need coral reefs, because
contexts provide expectations which are the basis both
for public participation and artistic production. Hope
is imaginable when currents—not movements, which are
exclusivist, but currents—begin to form. Of course,
paintings don’t create contexts by themselves—there is
the audience. It would help if lovers of art could
develop a degree of immunity toward the kind of art
that claims to celebrate free-radical individualism
with no earthly ties—the very definition of freedom in
the society of strangers—because that’s what puts all
the eggs in the basket of public space. And we know
where that has brought us.
Despite the
insistence of a previous generation, America has never
and will never provide the comparatively seamless
cultural/social/political, wrap-around world of
Paris—the sort homogenous societies enjoy. But however
complex the hand we have been dealt is, the cards we
hold are our own. We can, with a less buffered and
sometimes wry consciousness, while honoring the
overarching neutral culture that we all share and
fully appreciating the level of culture it can attain,
experience through our Bournean cultural federation a
view of life and art that—like our democracy—is unique
and unparalleled in history.